L'Académie nouvelle

Vous souhaitez réagir à ce message ? Créez un compte en quelques clics ou connectez-vous pour continuer.
L'Académie nouvelle

Forum d'archivage politique et scientifique

Le Deal du moment :
LEGO Icons 10331 – Le martin-pêcheur
Voir le deal
35 €

    Yuk Hui, Towards A Relational Materialism

    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Admin


    Messages : 20739
    Date d'inscription : 12/08/2013
    Localisation : France

    Yuk Hui, Towards A Relational Materialism Empty Yuk Hui, Towards A Relational Materialism

    Message par Johnathan R. Razorback Sam 5 Aoû - 11:03

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Yuk_Hui

    "Matter is considered [by moderns] to be something to be mastered, dominated and controlled." (note 1 p.132)

    "In contrast to the vague demand of the memory of the machine, as a component
    of the digital cosmology advocated by philosophers such as Fredkin and Chaitin,
    media theories argue more precisely for a ‘digital materiality’. While being
    different from the digital philosophers’ approaches, these theorists tend not to
    differentiate the ‘immateriality’ of the digital and the materiality of its support,
    hence its condition of being material becomes synonym of its materiality.
    Among these proposals, I find Matthew Kirschenbaum’s analysis deserving
    of careful consideration. Instead of claiming that certain matter is the foundation of the digital universe, he starts from the analysis of technical objects;
    like peeling an onion, he starts by asking what their constituents are. In his
    book Mechanisms − New Media and the Forensic Imagination, Kirschenbaum
    (2008) describes two types of materiality. One he calls forensic materiality and
    the other formal materiality. With forensic materiality, he refers to the method
    of analysing traces in a computer, going beyond what is visible on the screen.
    He takes the disk image of the online game “Mystery House” as an example,
    and demonstrates what he calls a “forensic walk through”. Kirschenbaum shows
    the hexadecimal and ASCII representations of data inside the file with the open
    source software FishWings and analyses the structure of the disk from track to
    track and sector to sector. In doing so, he finds traces that are not visible on the
    screen, for example the disk image also contains remnants of Bob Bishop’s Dung
    Beetles game and a ground-to-air shooter Blitzkrieg. Kirschenbaum concludes
    that the Mystery_house.dsk:

    “becomes a multivalent forensic environment, one where all of these different levels of
    engagement  – player, pirate/cracker, postmortem investigator  – find their correspondences in the multiple layers of textual events that both drive the game as code and are explicitly thematized within its forensically charged spaces.” (Kirschenbaum 2008: 109)

    The researcher who performs this forensic analysis, is like a detective who
    examines the traces of a criminal scene, “every contact leaves traces” as he
    claimed in talk given ten years ago in the History of Material Texts workshop
    at the University of Pennsylvania (Kirschenbaum 2005). With the notion of
    ‘formal materiality’ he refers to the “normative condition of working in a digital
    environment” (ibid.). He suggests speaking of two types of formal materiality.
    The first type is the explicit form of digital writing. Kirschenbaum compares
    this with Nelson Goodman’s notion of allographic objects; like written text,
    they fulfil “their ontology in reproduction” (2008: 133). In contrast to the allographic object stands the autographic object; similarly to a painting, its meaning
    cannot be explicitly repeated. The difference between Goodman’s example of
    the written text and digital writing is that digital writing has the “state of the art error detection and correction” which allow it to sustain an ideal allographic
    environment.
    The second type of formal materiality, according to Kirschenbaum, can
    be seen in standardised formats such as JPEG, MPEG and predefined logic of
    the application. In the footnote of the introduction, Kirschenbaum (2008: 9)
    refers to Johanna Drucker’s definition of materiality in The Visible Word: Experimental Typography and Modern Art, 1909–1923. For Drucker, materiality is
    considered as “two major intertwined strands: that of a relational, insubstantial, and non-transcendent difference and that of a phenomenological, apprehendable, immanent substance” (ibid.). In other words, materiality is defined
    by the dialectics of the objective reality and the subjective experience (varying
    from subjective to intersubjective). Kirschenbaum (ibid.) however, criticises that
    Katherine Hayles and Drucker’s notion of materiality is only limited to what he
    calls ‘forensic materiality’.
    Even though Kirschenbaum’s analytic method of layering is very relevant
    and the methodology of grounding his theory in objects is plausible, his critique
    of Drucker and Hayles’ concept of materiality still has to be reconsidered. The
    feminist theorists attempted to extend the notion of materiality from technical
    objects to embodiment, which exceeds the material scheme of technical objects
    upon the point of their invention (Hayles 1999). Kirschenbaum’s approach rather
    emerged from the tradition of textual studies. In contrast, Drucker and Hayles
    have suggested a larger scope in order to look at the question of materiality.
    While Kirschenbaum is probably right to say that Hayles misses “the computationally specific phenomenon of formal materiality, the simulation or modelling
    of materiality via programmed software processes” (2008: 9), a similar critique
    cannot be applied to Drucker’s analysis of typography, since ‘formal materiality’
    is exactly the condition of any phenomenological experience.
    We can also observe that what characterises Kirschenbaum’s analysis is a
    regression from the abstract concept of the digital to the endless layers of concrete
    matters. This can be read in great contrast to digital physics. Rather than starting
    from the One, Kirschenbaum starts with the Many. Unlike digital physics or
    digital philosophy which addresses the composition of bits, Kirschenbaum’s
    approach seeks a material base on which the digital can be recognized and
    embedded, through the decomposition of objects. ‘Regression’ however does not
    imply that this is a ‘bad’ development; instead, it indirectly avoids addressing the
    digital by addressing its conditions. For example, one can go from one condition
    to an outer condition layer by layer, and finally one will end up at the level of
    silicones, and probably also further to the sources of energy, etc. However, the
    speculative question remains, until when and to which level shall the forensic
    operation proceed?
    Furthermore, one will find that this analysis can actually be effectively
    applied to any type of technical object, and does not necessarily contribute to the
    clarification of the digital. Gilbert Simondon mentions a similar insight: with
    regards to the manufacture of a needle in Great Britain, he writes that, without
    exaggeration, the quality of the needle expresses the degree of perfection of the
    nation’s industry (Simondon 2012: 90). However, in the thought of Simondon, there are two important concepts that lead to a third inquiry into digital materiality. The first concept is relation; the second concept is concretisation, which
    effectively sublates the difference between the digital and the support of the
    digital, which characterise the above approaches. As a point of departure from
    digital physics and digital textuality, I would like to outline a third and progressive approach of analysis based on a particular reading of Simondon, which I
    am tempted to call a ‘relational materialism’. The last example on XML that
    Kirschenbaum gave in order to explain formal materiality would be a perfect
    example to understand relational materiality." (pp.135-137)

    "While we can see that the two abovementioned approaches either start with or end
    up with substance, this approach is an attempt to move away from substance to
    relations. Or more precisely, the aim of such relational materiality is to overcome
    the hylomorphism proposed by Aristotle, and to see how the development of
    technicity distances itself from this analysis.
    Hylomorphism is a substantialist thinking: in this context, being can be
    comprehended in terms of matter and form. The problem of the substantialist
    view is that it limits the question of becoming to the realm of predicates; in
    other words, there is only change in quality and quantity but not substance.
    The concept of substance as essence [ousia] refers back to Aristotle. In Categories, Aristotle (350 BCE a) calls this the support [hypokeimenon] and later in
    Metaphysics (350 BCE b) it is called form [eidos]. I see relations as the possibility to overcome this substantialist view, since a relational analysis will displace
    substance from the centre of being (however substance as a concept is hardly
    eliminated and it is still central to some construction of formal ontologies). This
    possibility can already be seen in Aristotle’s own writings. Aristotle in Categories describes Relative, ‘towards something’ (τὰ πρός τι), as one of the 9 accidents
    of the substance. By the end the section, the Stagirite doubted if substance is
    itself relative – he tried to show that primary substance is self-sufficient (e.g.
    man, horse), but he was not quite sure about secondary substance (e.g. hand,
    head): “[…] it may be questioned whether it is true that no substance is relative,
    as seems to be the case, or whether exception is to be made in the case of certain
    secondary substances” (Aristotle 350 BCE a). In Metaphysics Book V, Aristotle
    continues his analysis of three types of relations: identical relations (e.g. whiter,
    twice, longer), causal relations (heating and being heated) and psychological
    relations (knowing and the object to be known). Here it is worth repeating the
    questions posed by the medieval metaphysicians resulting from the interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics: what kind of being are relations? The peculiarity of
    relation (in comparison with other accidents) provoked his interpreters, notably
    Thomas Aquinas and Duns Scotus to name relation the weakest being (ens debilissimum). We can reiterate the question posed by the realists and reductionists
    of the medieval theologians: is relation ‘real being’ in the sense of substantial
    beings (which is a res), or just like other accidental beings (which have esse), or even weaker, meaning that they exist only as ratio or modus essendi (reason,
    mode of being)." (pp.137-138)

    "It was not possible to demonstrate the materiality of relation (as res) in the
    time of these medieval thinkers, and it remained largely a speculation and an
    attempt to solve the trinitarian problem [...] If we can talk about a relational materialism, it is because relation as a
    real being that is made possible by a general tendency of technology, consisting
    in the materialisation of all sorts of relations by rendering the invisibles visible
    and in measurable forms. For example, writing puts thoughts and perceptions on paper; pulleys, wheels and chains concretise imaginary movements
    in mechanical terms; the vapour engine instantiates flows of energy in the
    relations between water, fuels, pipes and gears; one could give similar examples
    for electricity, nuclear energy, etc. While in the digital environment, we can
    observe a more intensive process of materialisation of relation, in terms of data." (p.138)

    "Materialism in general did not pay much attention to relational materiality. Among the contemporary materialists, Karen Barad is probably closest to this conceptualisation." (p.138)

    "Russell criticised the fact that mathematics has inherited the philosophical
    error that an object has to be thought of in terms of subject-predicate propositions. Instead Russell proposed to move relation out of the Aristotelian ontology:
    “This view is derived, I think, probably unconsciously, from a philosophical error: it has
    always been customary to suppose relational propositions less ultimate than class-propositions (or subject-predicate propositions, with which class-propositions are habitually
    confounded), and this has led to a desire to treat relations as a kind of classes.” (Russell
    1937: §24)
    Let us consider a simple example: “Heidegger knows Bertrand Russell” or “I
    am taller than you”  – it is impossible to think of these statements in terms
    of subject-predicate class-proposition (‘I’ and ‘Russell’ cannot be reduced to a
    class-proposition; besides, both of us belong to the class “human being”), but
    there is still a need for an independent mathematical treatment of such statements. As Russell suggests, they could be expressed in the form ‘xRy’, in which
    ‘x’ is understood as the referent, ‘y’ as the relatum and ‘R’ as the relata (ibid.:
    §29). It seems worth pointing out the implications of this regarding the development of a relational database. Such thinking gave rise to a relational calculus,
    which was further developed in modern mathematics and computer science
    into two branches: Tuple Relational Calculus and Domain Relational Calculus.
    The Tuple Relational Calculus was introduced by the mathematician and information scientist Edgar F. Codd in the 1960s. It is part of the relational model,
    which in turn is the foundation of the Relational Database.

    Relation still consists of one of the core philosophical questions today;
    furthermore it emerges from a pure metaphysical concept to a concrete and
    material concept. In fact, Barad is critical of Russell’s notion of relation, since
    she announced that: “I present a relational ontology that rejects the metaphysics
    of relata, of “words” and “things” (Barad 2003: 812). However Barad is a science
    scholar, but not a technology scholar, and this is the limit of her thinking when
    she reproaches the linguistic turn and overlooks that even language is taking
    a new form of materialisation, especially in databases, in artificial intelligence,
    and, in the semantic web. If an operational and modulative metaphysics is
    grounded in relations, as Simondon and Gaston Bachelard have shown, then
    we will have to confront immediately the media technologies and the political
    economy of such relations. I further propose to understand relations in terms
    of what Simondon calls concretisation, by which what is non-material becomes
    material, notably causalities." (p.139)

    "Simondon lived at a time when
    the principles of quantum physics were used for the development of electronic
    devices, hence his examples are often focused around diodes, triodes, tetrodes,
    pentodes, etc., whereas today this is generally taken for granted. His understanding of technical object is also limited by the working principles of these
    devices, which depend mainly on physical contacts. Let us consider a diode: the
    operation of a diode depends on the transmission of electrons from the anode
    to the cathode, so is a triode, which in addition to the anode and cathode, puts a
    gate in between them to amplify the current. The physical contact as the foundation of the reciprocal causality is displaced by a causality operated through data.
    I use the word “displace” instead of “replace”, since it is not really replaced, we
    can never replace a causality based on physical contacts, but rather within the
    dynamic of the technical development, it becomes less and less the core part.
    Each epoch has its own media technologies of concretisation. The epoch
    of the digital is the epoch of the concretisation of relations in terms of data and
    metadata (i.e. data about data). Data (which for me is essential to the understanding of the digital) becomes the new material medium of operation. It is
    for this reason, that I separate digital objects from technical objects according
    to Simondon, though my reading of digital objects inherits the spirit of Simondon’s analysis. When we consider the development of the relational database and
    the technical lineage of mark-up languages from GML, SGML, HTML, XML,
    and Web ontologies as proposed by the semantic web, we see that the question of
    relations stands out above other concerns." (p.140)

    "The core idea of the semantic web is to build a system in which all the data can be
    structured according to predefined schemes or web ontologies. As I have shown
    with the abovementioned example, the ontologies or schemes define already
    “publisher”, “publication date”, “role” and hence it will be possible “[…] to automatise the search of information and to ease the navigation of data” (Tim BernersLee 1998). Everything on the web can be regarded as a resource, and is denoted
    with an URI (Universal Resource Indicator). In other words, we could say that
    it is a web of logic; however, this does not mean that the web should become a
    consistent logical system (since it also produces problems of ambiguity). Instead
    it is a web of materialised relations, which can be the URI or the comparison
    between any two attributes, even when the relation only says “different from”." (p.141)

    "A relational materialism is only explicit under digital conditions, since relation has been always considered to be mediated –it is grasped by a subject that comprehends it. In contrast, for digital materiality, the subjective grasp of relation is no longer the condition and this materialism is rendered visible through digital concretisation.
    Datum, means given ; the French word donnée retains this meaning. However, what is now data is no longer given, but has to be mediated, as if this data is already considered as relations." (p.141)

    "To invent a new concept of matter, is also to reinvent a new metaphysics
    and probably also a technological (post-)humanism in the spirit of Simondon
    (though there is no trace that Lyotard has read Simondon). Hence Lyotard
    preferred to conceptualise it as interaction rather than creation, as he writes

    “[…] if you say creation, that means that you prohibit the other metaphysics that I evoked
    earlier: a metaphysics in which, precisely, man is not a subject facing the world of objects,
    but only – and this ‘only’ seems to me to be very important – only a sort of synapse, a
    sort of interactive clicking together of the complicated interface between fields wherein
    particle elements flow via channels of waves” (Lyotard 1984: 9).
    What does Lyotard mean by interaction here? Interaction signifies an ontology
    of transmission of message without end, in which
    “man is not the origin of messages, but rather sometimes the receiver, sometimes the
    referent, sometimes a code, sometimes a support for the message, or sometimes the
    message itself and the plasticity of human means that this famous communicational
    structure looks like not something stable but instead something on which the identities
    can no longer be fixed” (ibid.: 10).

    The question of language was fundamental to the conceptualisation of Lyotard’s
    formulation of new matter, especially since telecommunication technology had
    created a new materiality of language between senders and receivers, and more
    fundamentally served as the foundation of the postmodern turn. Furthermore,
    one can speculate that the concept of interaction exists far before the digital. For
    what reason does it re-emerge? My postulation is that the digital renders visible
    and makes explicit a relational materialism: that the reflection on language
    allows Lyotard to develop an ontology of the material or immaterial according to
    the model of telecommunication. The new materiality, as we can see, has to be
    mapped in the telecommunication model according to these 5 categories.

    1. Matériau (support): by what medium speaks the message;
    2. Matériel (receiver): to which destination speaks the message;
    3. Maternité (sender): in which name speaks the message;
    4. Matière (referent): of what speaks the message;
    5. Matrice (code): in what way speaks the message." (p.142)

    "What underlies these 5 categories of Mât is relational. It demonstrates a frame
    work to understand the abstract concept of the digital in concrete and material
    terms. There are several important points one should keep in mind. Firstly,
    the maternity is no longer taken as the pure receptacle, which has to be shaped
    by the idea, but rather it takes the form of a sender. Secondly the new material
    is distributed throughout different components which cannot be separated;
    among them there are two relations: one is from the sender (maternité) to the
    receiver (matériel), the other is from the message to its referent (matière). Such a
    relationality is carried by the support (matériau) according to the coding or rules
    of coding (matrice). Thirdly, I would like to reflect on the referent, since it is also
    probably something we may want to update after Lyotard.
    Gottlob Frege in his famous article Sense and Reference [Sinn und Bedeutung],
    distinguishes words according to ‘sense’ and ‘reference’. For example, morning
    star and evening star have different senses, but they all have the same reference
    which is the Venus (Frege 1948: 211-212). In this conception, the referent is
    always something outside, it is not carried by the sense, but rather the sense
    only points it to the reference. For Frege, Sinn and Bedeutung merely operate on
    the level of signification, but it is only in the new material that Lyotard sees the
    transformation of language. Namely, the most systematic medium of signification is turned into materialised computational operations. In a documentary
    dedicated to Les Immatéraux, towards the very end of the film, Lyotard proposed
    that “language is the most immaterial system that matter has succeeded in
    forming” [le langage est le système le plus immatériel que la matière ait réussi à
    former] (Lyotard 1986). We may suspect that Lyotard wrote this in the spirit of
    the “linguistic turn” that Barad criticised, however, when re-contextualising it
    in the relational materiality that I have described, language takes a different
    form. We can probably simply replace the word “language” in Lyotard’s quote
    with the word “digital”, since underlying the abstract and immaterial concept of
    the digital is the most concrete and material system.
    Considering the example of data technology, we can see that the referent
    is materialised and rendered explicit. To a certain extent, it is similar to what
    Kirschenbaum writes about Nelson Goodman’s distinction between the allographic and the autographic object which was mentioned before, but here the
    referent is even more explicit and systematic. For example, the semantic web is
    a constant process of integrating all materials, no matter what granularity, into
    resources, and each resource is given an URI (Universal Resource Indicator). So
    for example, now the morning star and evening star can all become resources
    such as their referent Venus, and these relations can be named by predicates, for
    example _is or _refers_to.

    If this logic is well followed, then we can see that such a relational materialism does not only follow a progressive development of technicity, but also
    embeds a resistance against the modernist and substantialist view of matter.
    If human beings can also be interpreted through the Mât-system, on the one
    hand we see that they become unmasterable since they are no longer created,
    but rather emerge through interaction. On the other hand, when human beings
    become part of this system, they are within it and part of it, and therefore human beings are no longer able to elevate themselves to any ‘transcendent’ plane. In
    order to generalise this connection without losing specificity, one could say that
    a relational materialism is only possible, if 1) nature is progressively overcome
    and transformed in material terms (this is another aspect of the maternity of
    matter – the materialisation of relations which turns significations into material
    connections: matériau, matière, matrice), and 2) the receptacle itself becomes
    relational, in the sense that it can be analysed in terms of relations which are
    real, and such relations find their common medium with the embodied experience, which in turn affects its own structure.
    A relational analysis is close to what Kirschenbaum calls formal materiality,
    since most of these relations emerge from formal structures. However, we have
    to consider not only how structures determine relations, but also how relations
    determine structures: the inter/intra-action between 1) and 2) that traverse two
    orders of magnitude. This recursive relationality was firstly foregrounded by the
    theory of feedback in cybernetics; however, such feedback should not be understood as general term, but rather according to the scale, order and magnitude of
    the investigated object (e.g., social networks, nanotechnology, synthetic biology,
    etc.). It would have been impossible to analyse the same type of relations in the
    time of steam engines, but it is possible with regards to digital writing which
    possesses a totally different order of granularity. It is also due to this reason, that
    Kirschenbaum’s reading of Drucker’s materiality as mere forensic materiality
    is not justified – since with this ‘organic form’ materiality has become richer
    than just data records. By organic form, I mean the reciprocal relation between
    relations and the structure. Moreover, for Drucker, the materiality of embodiment is relevant (which this is not the case for Kirschenbaum). If we acknowledge this rapport between relations and technologies, it seems possible to derive
    an analytic tool based on this formulation (between relations and matter), which
    goes beyond any dogmatic account of digital materiality." (pp.143-144)
    -Yuk Hui, "Towards A Relational Materialism", Digital Culture and Society, Vol. 1, Issue 1, 2015



    _________________
    « La question n’est pas de constater que les gens vivent plus ou moins pauvrement, mais toujours d’une manière qui leur échappe. » -Guy Debord, Critique de la séparation (1961).

    « Rien de grand ne s’est jamais accompli dans le monde sans passion. » -Hegel, La Raison dans l'Histoire.

    « Mais parfois le plus clair regard aime aussi l’ombre. » -Friedrich Hölderlin, "Pain et Vin".


      La date/heure actuelle est Dim 17 Nov - 15:28