L'Académie nouvelle

Vous souhaitez réagir à ce message ? Créez un compte en quelques clics ou connectez-vous pour continuer.
L'Académie nouvelle

Forum d'archivage politique et scientifique

Le deal à ne pas rater :
Pokémon Évolutions Prismatiques : coffrets et dates de sortie de ...
Voir le deal

    Otto Neurath

    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Admin


    Messages : 20709
    Date d'inscription : 12/08/2013
    Localisation : France

    Otto Neurath Empty Otto Neurath

    Message par Johnathan R. Razorback Mer 16 Aoû - 13:04

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Otto_Neurath

    https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/neurath/index.html

    "Neurath was a social scientist and activist, scientific philosopher and maverick leader of the Vienna Circle who championed the so-called scientific attitude and the Unity of Science movement. He denied any value to philosophy over and above the pursuit of work on science, within science and for science and society. And scientific results, he argued, are not logically fixed, securely founded on experience or can be ordered in a System of knowledge. Uncertainty, decision and cooperation are intrinsic to scientific practice. From this naturalistic, holistic and pragmatist viewpoint, philosophy investigates the conditions of the possibility of science as apparent in science itself, namely, in terms of physical, biological, sociological, historical, psychological, linguistic, logical or mathematical conditions. His views on the language, method and unity of science were led throughout by his interest in the social life of individuals and their well-being. To theorize about society is inseparable from theorizing for and within society. Science is in every sense a social and historical enterprise and helps society understand the past, explore possibilities and engineer the future. It is as much about social objectives as it is about physical objects, and about social realizations as much as about empirical reality. Objectivity and rationality, epistemic values to constrain scientific thought, were radically social. His contributions to visual education –based on pictorial languages–, museology, urban planning, and political economy –especially on collective welfare, ecological economics and the unavoidability of multi-criterial evaluation– constitute concrete legacies that have regained relevance, interest and urgency.

    Otto Neurath was born on 10 December 1882 in Vienna. He was the son of Gertrud Kaempffert and Wilhelm Neurath, a Hungarian Jewish political economist and social reformer. While benefitting from his father’s vast polymathic library, in Vienna he studied literature, mathematics, physics, history, philosophy and economics (although he formally enrolled at the University of Vienna only for two semesters in 1902–3). Next he followed the social scientist Ferdinand Tönnies’s advice to move to Berlin, where he received a doctoral degree in history of economics in 1906. He studied under leaders of the so-called Young German Historical School Eduard Meyer and Gustav Schmoller and he was awarded the degree for two studies of economic history of antiquity, one on Cicero’s De Officiis and the other with an emphasis on the non-monetary economy of Egypt.

    On his return to Vienna, he joined other economists such as Joseph Schumpeter and Ludwig von Mises at postdoctoral seminars led by theoriests of Carl Menger’s so-called Austrian School Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk and Friedrich von Wieser. At the time Neurath engaged ongoing debates over the unity of the sciences –especially the distinction between Naturwissenschaften and Geisteswisshenschaften–, the role of values in science and goals and methods of economics (Uebel 2004). The debates would prompt early views on the practice of science and inform his subsequent positions within scientific philosophy and logical empiricism.

    His first publications were in the history of political economy and logic, a subject he had formally learned at the University of Vienna. In the history of political economy, topics included the history of money and economic organizations in antiquity, and his publications included textbooks and readers either co-authored or co-edited with his first wife Anna Schapire-Neurath, expert in literature and social issues. The papers on logic focused on issues in algebraic logic and included one paper, of 1909, co-authored with his friend and second wife, Olga Hahn, a sister of the mathematician Hans Hahn (she shortly after received a doctorate for her logic work). Neurath’s subsequent theorizing on the social sciences and his contributions to debates on logical empiricism integrated both disciplines. With the mathematician Hans Hahn and the physicist Philip Frank, around 1910 Neurath formed in Vienna a philosophical discussion group focused on foundational crises in physics and mathematics and the philosophical ideas about science of Vienna’s positivist Ernst Mach and the French conventionalists Pierre Duhem, Abel Rey and Henri Poincaré. A great deal of philosophical and scientific concerns and insight were already in place in Neurath’s thinking and projects. With a grant from the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, a subsequent study of the Balkan Wars and then World War I led him to develop a theory of war economy as a natural (non-monetary) economy, or economy in kind, and to propose models for its peacetime implementation as a solution to endemic socio-economic problems of capitalism.

    In 1919 the short-lived Bavarian socialist government (November 1918-April 1919) appointed him head of the Central Planning Office. The fall of the subsequent Bavarian Soviet Republic in May 1919 got him expelled from his junior post teaching economic theory under Max Weber at Heidelberg University, where he had received his Habilitation in 1917. His program for full socialization of the economy was inspired by his studies of war economics and based on his theory of natural economy and a holistic requirement to bring different institutions and kinds of knowledge together in order to understand, predict and control the complex phenomena of the social world (see the supplementary material on Political Economy). His driving social concern was collective welfare or happiness, which he came to consider not a form of utiltarianisn but of Epicurean socialism.

    From 1921 until 1934 Neurath participated actively in the development of socialist politics, especially in housing and adult education, in so-called Red Vienna (on his political life, see Sandner 2014). He established the Social and Economic Museum of Vienna, where he developed and applied the ‘Vienna method’ of picture statistics and the ISOTYPE language (International System of Typographic Picture Education) (see the supplementary document on Visual Education). Like the thought of other Viennese philosophers such as Ludwig Wittgenstein and Karl Popper, Neurath’s philosophy was inextricably linked to pedagogy, logic, critique of language and, in Popper’s case, political thought. In 1928, with members of the Austrian Freethinkers Association and the Vienna City Council and the scientifically-trained members of the informal circle around the current holder of Mach’s University Chair, the philosopher Moritz Schlick (1924–29), Neurath helped found the Verein Ernst Mach, the Ernst Mach Association for the Promotion of Science Education. The publication in 1929 of an intellectual manifesto gave way to the formation of the Vienna Circle, whose narrower goal was the articulation and promotion of a scientific world-conception and logical empiricism (on the Viennese intellectual landscape, see Stadler 2001).

    When in 1934 the Austrian government allied itself with the German Nazi government, Neurath fled to the Netherlands. As a result, his local, Viennese, socialist Enlightenment project turned into an internationalist, intellectual and social-political project. He created the International Foundation for Visual Education in The Hague, with his assistants from Vienna, and spearheaded the International Unity of Science movement. The latter, inspired by a tradition culminating in the Enlightenment’s French Encyclopedists, launched the project of an Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Together with the pictorial languages, the scientific encyclopedia would promote scientific and social cooperation and progress at an international level. After Austria became part of the German Reich in 1938, even though living in the Netherlands, Neurath was considered a German citizen and a ‘half-Jew’ and he was not allowed to marry his ‘Aryan’ assistant Marie Reidemeister—after his second wife, Olga, had died in 1937. During this period, he travelled abroad, including the United States, where logical empiricism had become entangled with the Cold War political and intellectual debates and witch hunts (on the Cold War phase, see Reich 2005). Carnap and Charles Morris at the University of Chicago acted as his co-editors of the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. New York leftist intellectuals hosted him as an intellectual and political ally. And his maternal first cousin Waldemar Kaempffert, influential editor for The New York Times and Popular Science, introduced him as an international reformer and visionary, praising his science-oriented intellectual, social and educational ideas, especially his contribution to unity of science and visual language (see Reisch 2019). After the Nazi invasion of the Netherlands in 1940, Otto Neurath and Marie Reidemeister fled to England, on the small Seaman’s Hope. After nine months in an internment camp they resumed activities related to the Isotype language, public education and the unity of science. He died in Oxford on 22 December 1945 (on activities in the camp see Henning 2019; on activities after see Körber 2019 and Tuboly 2019).

    by 1910 Neurath had already been involved in debates on the issues of scientific unity and methodology. They were prompted by his research in economics as well as foundational issues in mathematics and physics and reading in positivism and conventionalism. His early metascientific, or philosophical, views developed along with his economic thinking and evolving historical context. In projects of socialized, planned economic reform and in his broader notion of economics, they featured interrelated concepts and concerns: unity, rationality, precision, possibility, planning, decision, control, construction –or engineering–, communication, coordination, history and their social dimensions and applications. The same issues –alongside illustrating references to boats and Robinson Crusoe– would later play a defining role in his epistemological and methodological contributions to logical empiricism (Nemeth 1991, Cat et al. 1991 and 1996 and Cat 2024).

    For instance: (1) a notion of theorizing in natural and social sciences, including history, based on the historical exploration of combinatorial possibilities and models, past and future; (2) the application in the social sciences of empirical goals and methods of the natural sciences; (3) a unifying public (objective and testable) language for scientific data and hypotheses, with a private-language argument anticipating Wittgenstein’s own and also illustrated by the case of Robinson Crusoe; (4) the evaluation and choice of data and hypotheses characterized by a logical under-determination of hypotheses by data and the conventional and pragmatic aspect of rational decision-making and control (with a role for so-called auxiliary motives); (5) the historical, social, cooperative, planned and constructive (engineering) dimensions of scientific research (a ‘republic of scientists’); (6), connectedly, a holistic approach to scientific knowledge and its application in the form of encyclopedic unification without hierarchical systems as a tool for successful prediction and engineering of events in a complex world –an ‘encyclopedia model’, by establishing cross-connections among disciplines, as in a Crusonian archipelago: a ‘great, rather badly coordinated mass of statements’ in which at best ‘systems develop like little islands, which we must try to enlarge’ (Neurath 1936/1983, 153)–; and (7) the social relevance of scientific philosophy, especially the unification and demarcation of science against metaphysics.

    Regarding unification, Neurath endorsed a broader notion of economics based on symbolic (or logical) rather than merely quantitative precision and a historical perspective that included the use of empirical methods and theoretical distinctions common in the natural sciences; the combination served the purpose of comparing and classifying past cases and future possibilities (Neurath 1910). In addition, Neurath’s proposal of a moneyless war economy sought to maximize human happiness rather than private profit, and was based on a set of incommensurable indicators rather than the uniform monetary measurement unit. An economic plan for a socialized economy required the consideration of the different indicators that in turn required a holistic organization of information and individuals to coordinate decisions and action (rather than a market). Prediction and action required different forms of unity.

    This engineering value of unity applied equally to political governance and scientific action, since both are collective and pragmatic endeavors. According to Neurath, ‘scientific theories are sociological events’ (Neurath 1932a/1983, 88), and, since ‘our thinking is a tool’, in this case the ‘modern scientific world-conception’ aims to ‘create a unified science that can successfully serve all transforming activity’ (Neurath 1930/1983, 42). In both cases, Neurath noted, ‘common planned action is possible only if the participants make common predictions’ and group predictions yield more reliable results; therefore, he concluded, ‘common action presses us toward unified science’ (Neurath 1931/1973, 407). Indeed, all along, for Neurath scientific attitude and solidarity (and socialism) go together (Neurath 1928/1973, 252).

    Economic planning was a matter of consideration of possibilities and making rational decisions. But for Neurath, practical and theoretical rationality was not a matter of mechanical, objective calculation or reasoning alone –especially in the absence of full insight and a uniform quantitative monetary unit. In a study of psychology of decisions he dismissed such a standard of rationality as “pseudo-rationalism” (Neurath 1913). Planning was a pragmatic (social) engineering problem, namely, a matter of construction and control, and decisions among alternative possibilities that required judgement, external goals or just a coin flip –auxiliary motives (Neurath 1913). Both rationality and the irreducibly social perspective were matters of debate among economists, including Karl Marx, and illustrated, also by Neurath, with references to the fictional figure of Robinson Crusoe stranded on an island.

    Along similar lines, we can place Neurath’s contributions to the Vienna Circle’s project of a scientific world-conception and logical empiricism in context of his evolving political epistemology. Considerations of knowledge at the theoretical or practical service of politics played a central role in his work on economic planning. He envisioned the role of rationality and the coordination of information and political goals mentioned above also in relation to socialist democratic model of participation of citizen workers. Deliberation and decision making required communication, also of social and economic information. For such education purpose, at the service of participation, Neurath designed a pictorial language (Sandner 2014, Groß 2019 and Nemeth 2019; see also supplementary material on visual education). This discursive approach to communication of knowledge and decision making was also part of his objection and alternative to models such as Hayek’s based on the role of markets and prices (Hayek 1935, Neurath 1942). Neurath’s economic planning was neither technocratic nor dictatorial (Chaloupek 2008). But it relied on expert proposals.

    In exile in the 1940s the socialist internationalism of his social models turned more liberal, combining international planning for freedom and liberal democracy. Neurath addressed the role of experts and the distinction between esoteric and exoteric, or lay, knowledge and promoted the democratization of knowledge: ‘what we call democracy implies a rejection of experts in making decision[s]’ (Neurath 1996, 251). But how much democratization required or could achieve in such checks on expert power has been debated (Wussow 2021).

    Neurath formulated his empiricist epistemology through the 1930s in similar terms of checks and controls. Data statements he called control statements; and the dynamics of knowledge formation and revision was a matter of formal and empirical controls. Relative to the resulting unity in a theory or body of knowledge, metaphysical statements could be identified and rejected as uncontrolled and isolated

    3.1 Language
    Neurath’s later views on the language and method of science expressed his simultaneous response to earlier problems in the social sciences and to philosophical issues addressed by the Vienna Circle between 1928 and 1934. A primary aim of the Vienna Circle was to account for the objectivity and intelligibility of scientific method and concepts and to demarcate scientific from metaphysical statements. Their philosophical approach was to adopt what the Circle member Gustav Bergmann called the linguistic turn, namely, to investigate the formal or structural, logical and linguistic framework of scientific knowledge. Within this framework members of the Circle pursued the aims of intelligibility and demarcation by means of two connected conditions of meaning and meaningfulness. The former –stronger– often was formulated mainly by Moritz Schlick (after Wittgenstein) as a condition of empirical verification. The latter –weaker– was a related semantic condition of empirical verifiability, formulated mainly by Rudolf Carnap in different ways over time, and was supplemented by a syntactic condition of formal or grammatical correctness (Uebel 2007). The formal approach encompassed logicism and logical analysis as views about the formation, interpretation, justification and acceptance especially of theoretical statements. The problem of empiricism became then the problem of coordination between the formal theoretical structures and the records of observations in such a way that it also offered an explication of how scientific knowledge can and should be formally constructed (especially in logic and mathematics), empirically grounded (except logic and mathematics), and thereby understood, evaluated and accepted.

    Sources of Neurath’s attention to language are multiple. Besides Neurath’s own early interest in logic and classical and ancient languages, the value of attention to language was familiar to Neurath from the Austrian fin-de-siècle culture of critique of language (Janik and Toulmin 1973), his interest (and his first wife’s) in literature, especially in Goethe (Zemplen 2006), Marx and Engels’ attention to the radically social dimension of language (and its relation to money), the internationalist and utopianists efforts at introducing new universal languages such as Volapük and Esperanto, the emphasis on signs and universal languages – to be known as pasigraphy – in the scholastic and rationalist philosophical traditions, in the traditions of empirical taxonomies and in the interest in universal language as instrument of knowledge and social order in the Enlightenment, a semiotic tradition in scientific epistemology including Helmholtz, Mach, Duhem and Peirce (Cat 2019) and the sociologist Ferdinand Tönnies’s formal approach to sociology and social signs (Tönnies 1899–1900 and Cartwright et al. 1996). The significance of the internationalist and philosophical projects of so-called pasigraphy were acknowledged also by Carnap. More “scientific” sources were recent technical developments in logic, philosophy of science and the foundation of mathematics often claiming Leibniz as a precursor (Leibniz’s logic and project of a universal characteristic had become widely recognized by the late nineteenth century (Peckhaus 2012)). Leading figures in such developments were Frege, Hilbert, Whitehead, Russell and Wittgenstein.

    Russell led the application of the new method of analytic philosophy that required solving or dissolving philosophical problems by analyzing their formulation in a more perspicuous technical, logical language. His student Wittgenstein, in turn, introduced a linguistic philosophy that limited the world to the scope of the application of an ideal symbolic languages, or calculus. As a result, the sole task of philosophy was, according to Wittgenstein, the critique of language in the form of an activity of clarification, without yielding a distinctive philosophical body of knowledge or set of propositions.

    Looking to the rationalist traditions of Descartes and Leibniz, Jean van Heijenoort and Jaakko Hintikka have distinguished between two views of language that are relevant to the new linguistic turn (Mormann 1999): language as calculus (LC) and language as universal medium (LUM). The LC tradition, illustrated by Tarski’s views, aligned itself with the Cartesian ideal of a transparent language, with clear and distinctive meaning and explicit, mechanical combination and rule-following that extended to its use in reasoning. There are many possible constructed languages and each is an interpreted calculus with different possible semantics. The LUM tradition adopted the idea of a single actual or ideal language and one semantic or interpretation, to be elucidated, with no possibility of representing its relation to the world from outside. Views by Frege, who pointed to Leibniz on language and reasoning, and Wittgenstein illustrate this tradition, which in turn accommodates two versions, a Cartesian one (Frege and Russell) and a non-Cartesian one (Wittgenstein).

    Members of the Vienna Circle pursued their shared philosophical goals through the discussion of language and its application in cognition. Their respective views on epistemic matters relied on different views on language and philosophy. Carnap and Neurath shared an epistemological naturalism –without a priori foundations– with a constructive metascientific standpoint; philosophy would require a scientific metatheory within the boundaries of unified science (Uebel 2007 and Bentley 2023). The difference rested in the goals and scientific disciplines they favored. Carnap looked to formal tools such as logic and syntax and sought rational reconstruction; Neurath looked to the empirical sciences, from psychology to history and sociology and sought pragmatic guidance to provide and improve scientists’ tools and decisions –and social applications.

    Carnap’s conversion to semantics in the early 1930s took him to the LC Cartesian tradition seeking a universal language of rational reconstruction he had previously recognized in the language of physics. Neurath, by contrast, modeled his anti-metaphysical unification of the sciences in the LUM tradition, on a public –empirically testable and socially effective– universal mixed language he eventually called a ‘universal jargon’, with descriptions of spatio-temporal arrangements and connections he called physicalism, historically contingent use of vague and ordinary terms (see below). In this context Neurath adopted a militant syntacticism, avoiding semantic entities and properties such as truth-values, reference and correspondence. He unsurprisingly opposed and denounced Carnap’s defense of semantics and Schlick’s talk of reality as metaphysical (Anderson 2019) –engaging along the way in heated terminological disputes that ignored Carnap’s commitment to ontological neutrality (Carus 2019).

    Again, the Circle’s projects shared the aforementioned focus on language and experience. The linguistic approach was adopted as a philosophical tool in order to explicate the rationality and the objectivity—that is, inter-subjectivity—and communicability of thought. Lacking the transcendental dimension of Kant’s metaphysical apparatus, attention to language extended to non-scientific cases such as ‘ordinary language philosophy’ in Oxford. In the context of logical empiricism, the formal dimension of knowledge was thought to be manifest particularly in the exactness of scientific statements.

    For Schlick, knowledge proper, whether of experience or transcendent reality, was such only by virtue of form or structure—‘only structure is knowable’. For Carnap, in addition, the formal dimension possessed distinct methodological values: it served the purpose of logical analysis and rational reconstruction of knowledge and helped expose and circumvent ‘pseudo-philosophical’ problems around metaphysical questions about reality (his objections to Heidegger appealed to failures of proper logical formulation and not just empirical verification). In 1934 he proposed as the task of philosophy the metalinguistic analysis of logical and linguistic features of scientific method and knowledge (the ‘thesis of metalogic’). For Neurath, this approach helped purge philosophy of deleterious metaphysical nonsense and dogmatism, and acknowledged the radically social nature of language and science. His approach to demarcation through significance or meaningfulness was pragmatic and looser than that of fellow Circle members. His approach to verification, or empirical control, and formal control of knowledge claims was contextual, pragmatic and holistic. He defended a corresponding distinction between controlled, integrated statements (unification) and uncontrolled, isolated metaphysical ones –or of some other kind. But this required a uniform language for scientific collaboration that he thought contained unavoidable vague terms and required uniform notational standards, even in logic.

    Neurath’s plan was for a unified science against metaphysics, and this involved a plan to police the proper unifying, metaphysics-free language. The negative track of the plan was effectively carried out by the development and adoption of a list of ‘dangerous terms,’ which he sometimes referred to, semi-jokingly, as an index verborum prohibitorum: a list of forbidden terms such as ‘I’, ‘ego’, ‘substance,’ etc. (Neurath 1933, Neurath 1940/1984, 217). The positive track was the adoption of the universal language of physicalism: ‘metaphysical terms divide—scientific terms unite’ (1935, 23, orig. ital.).

    3.2 Language, logic and rationality
    Logic has long received philosophical attention as a language regulated by strict rules of reasoning, thus setting standards of clarity, rigor and rationality. Leibniz had given modern philosophical currency to the pasigraphic notion of a universal characteristic or Alphabet of Thought that both expressed reality and operated as a logical calculus of reasoning. In the Cartesian spirit, language and reason were inseparable instruments of knowledge and mathematical, logical and philosophical methods were identical. In the late nineteenth century and the early twentieth, Leibniz’s project became a common reference in works in mathematical logic. Not only did Frege see his philosophy of language and mathematical logic within this tradition, as did Peano; Russell penned a landmark study and logicians such as Ernst Schröder and Louis Couturat associated it distinctively with the development of algebraic logic since Boole, especially with Schröder’s own (Peckhaus 2012).

    Neurath enjoyed early attention and recognition for his logic work also reflected in early reminiscences of figures such as Popper and the mathematician Karl Menger. Perhaps surprisingly now, mentions of Neurath’s and Olga Hahn’s papers were included by the logicians C.I. Lewis, in 1918, and Alonzo Church, in 1936, in their canonical bibliographies on symbolic logic (Lewis 1918 and Church 1936). Neurath kept algebraic logic and its symbolic dimension as a recurrent standard and resource, first in his earlier work on the social sciences and pictorial language, and subsequently in related contributions to the discussions that informed logical empiricism.

    Contrary to predominant accounts using attention to formal languages and logic to pit against each other wings and members of the logical empiricist movement, the symbolic logical standard may be considered a unifying framework for scientific philosophy that distinguished Neurath within it and not from it. It a unifying reference he willingly adopted when he coined the term ’logical empiricism.’ The differentiating role in Neurath’s positions can be identified in his shifting and progressively skeptical and critical attention to the standard and to his attention to algebraic logic rather than the newer logic familiar to Carnap from Frege’s and Russell’s works on logic and logicism.

    By the late nineteenth century, in Austria as well as Germany, algebraic logic had found a central place in the raging controversies over the relationship between science and philosophy and, in particular, between mathematics, logic and psychology. Neurath and Olga Hahn became acquainted with algebraic logic at the University of Vienna sometime around 1902–3, but it wasn’t until 1909, after Olga had become blind and Neurath was back in Vienna providing assistance, that she started working on algebraic logic for her doctorate in philosophy and they began their collaboration and separate publications. Neurath published four papers, one with Hahn (Neurath 1909a, 1909b and 1910a, and Hahn and Neurath 1909). Hahn separately published two others, the second submitted as her doctoral thesis (Hahn 1909 and 1910).

    Neurath’s logic writings focused on Schröder’s axiomatic systematization of algebraic logic, mainly in the monumental Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik (exakte Logik) (1890–95). There and in earlier writings, Schröder gave a fundamental role to the relation of subsumption and a law of duality. Subsumption was a part-whole relation defined over domains of objects. The law of duality established a systematic correspondence between theorems in terms of 1 and operation + and theorems in terms of 0 and operation x.

    The papers were concerned with the equality relations and fundamental status of axioms of the system of algebraic logic, dominant in the second half of the nineteenth century and modeled, they objected, too closely after mathematical operations and equations. It was developed as a calculus of statements (propositional logic) and domains, more generally. Neurath distinguished between expression and denotation of signs to distinguish different uses and interpretations of equality signs and interpret symbolic identities as univocal relations and redundant expressions and rules of substitution in the logical manipulation of signs. In particular, he distinguished between definitional equality, symbolic equality and identity equality. Most of the papers focused on the case of the property of commutativity (‘ab=ba’) and Schröder’s proof. Neurath rejected the proof as based on unjustified mathematical notational assumptions. In particular, the symbolic equality between symbols for the same relation between the same objects renders one symbol meaningless, or redundant. The commutativity result is merely a symbolic equality, a notational stipulation.

    In their joint paper, Hahn and Neurath also focused on the principle of duality as a basic symmetry principle for the generation of theorems for complementary domains and operations. They argued that duality is linked to the fundamental symmetric complementarity between positive and negative domains. It is a (meta)logical, not an empirical, inductive principle; so understood it could be applied more clearly and systematically. Neurath and Hahn’s attention to the relativity of fundamental logical axioms and symbolic notation paralleled similar conventionalist discussions in geometry, especially by Poincaré.

    Rational decision-making became a central issue in Neurath’s economic thinking. All the more so when Neurath noted the limitations of the calculation of collective comparative pleasure and displeasure associated with different sets of goods (Neurath 1912). It is hardly surprising then that, even before engaging in debates over the rationality of socialist economic planning, Neurath continued examining reasoning and rationality –theoretical and practical– more generally. In Vienna, the intellectual and social project was connected to the spirit of the Enlightenment. In an essay of 1913, ‘The lost wanderers of Descartes and the auxiliary motive (on the psychology of decision)’ (Neurath 1913) he criticized Descartes’ theoretical rationalism and examined his psychology of action to explore decision-making under uncertainty. He introduced a general distinction, for theoretical and practical reasoning, between rationality and pseudo-rationalism. He dismissed as pseudorationalism the ideal of replacing instinct and authority with formal reasoning and calculation as the sole and sufficient method of decision-making based on conclusions without awareness of cognitive limitations or incomplete insight.

    Instead, he argued, conclusions about courses of action, including the acceptance of hypotheses, are typically in need of supplementing with additional considerations he called auxiliary motives. The recourse is justified pragmatically. In general, what counts as an auxiliary motive might be external motives, values or conventions (goals or constraints as reasons) and pure decision procedures including the drawing of lots –since making any decision is more important than any decision made– (on the pure proceduralist interpretation see Bentley 2023). This volutntarism, decisionism and pragmatism became central to his contributions to the scientific epistemology of logical empiricism. He referred then also to unavoidable extra-logical factors (Neurath 1934).

    3.3 Scientific and linguistic epistemology
    Kant had delivered the latest grand attempt to address the relation between science and philosophy, by taking the former to provide objective empirical knowledge (exact, universal and necessary) and giving to the latter knowledge the task of laying out the a priori conditions of intelligibility and possibility of such knowledge as the sole, critical scope of metaphysics and legitimate exercise of reason. Kant’s standard of a priori, an expression of rationality, was challenged and relativized by Frege, Russell and Whitehead’s notions of mathematical numbers grounded in logic, by models of non-Euclidean geometry and their analysis by Poincaré and by the new notions of space and time in Einstein’s relativity theories. Neither mathematics was synthetic nor physics seemed a priori; as a result, in the new scientific landscape the metaphysical category of synthetic a priori was dismissed as empty of content.

    With the scientific world-conception, logical empiricists followed in the footsteps and Helmholtz and Mach and considered a new post-Kantian problematic: investigating the possibility of objective empirical knowledge with a role for intellectual construction without universality or necessity, neither Kantian apriorism nor radical positivism. Logic, with scientific status linked to technical symbolism and the possibility of mathematics, was the sole last refuge for philosophy. The new problematic suggested a demarcation project with two inseparable tasks that were both descriptive and normative: a positive, unifying task to establish and promote the marks of scientific knowledge and the negative task to distinguish it from philosophy, especially the objects and concepts of metaphysics.

    According to logical empiricists a priori knowledge claims expressed in exact theory were circumscribed to the analytic. Yet they were voided of universality and necessity (Kant’s marks of the a priori) and deflated by Schlick and Reichenbach to the character of definitions and conventions (following Poincaré). They were true or valid only relatively and by construction. Synthetic knowledge claims were exclusively a posteriori, their contents and validity grounded in experience.

    The philosophical discussion that developed around the members of the Vienna Circle was associated with the formulation of logical empiricism and the rallying cry of ‘unity of science against metaphysics.’But it cannot be adequately understood without taking into account the diversity of evolving projects it accommodated. Carnap’s and Neurath’s respective metascientific stance has been mentioned above. Carnap was much borrowed from the neo-Kantian tradition, Einstein’s theories of relativity, Husserl’s phenomenology, Frege’s logic and, i.e., Hilbertian axiomatic approach to mathematics as well as Russell’s own logicism and his philosophical project of logical constructions. He was concerned with the conditions of the possibility of objective knowledge, which he considered especially manifest in the formal exactness of scientific claims (Carnap 1928). Schlick borrowed from turn-of-the-century French conventionalists such as Rey, Duhem and Poincaré, Wittgenstein’s philosophy of representation of facts, as well as Einstein’s relativity theories and Hilbert’s implicit definitions and axiomatic approach to mathematics. He was interested in the meaning of terms in which actual scientific knowledge of reality is expressed, as well as its foundation on true and certain beliefs about reality (Schlick 1918, 1934). Also Reichenbach had been influenced by and borrowed from Einstein, neo-Kantianism and Hilbert’s axiomatics. Neurath borrowed, among others, fromm Mach, varieties of French conventionalism, especially Duhem’s, and varieties of social thought including Marxism. He sought to explore the empirical and historical conditions of scientific practice in both the natural and social sciences (Neurath 1931/1973, 1932a/1983). Outside the Vienna Circle, Popper borrowed from Hume, Kant and Austrian child psychology. He was interested in addressing the logical and normative issues of justification and demarcation of objective and empirical scientific knowledge, without relying on descriptive discussions of the psychology of subjective experience and meaning (Popper 1935/1951).

    The linguistic turn framed the examination of the controversial role of experience and the form of its expression and relation to hypotheses. In that respect an ensuing discussions of data or so-called protocol sentences concerned their linguistic characteristics and their epistemological status (Uebel 1992). It served the Circle’s purpose of ascertaining the source, evaluation and acceptance of human knowledge and rejecting metaphysics as nonsense—often dangerous nonsense (Carnap, Hahn and Neurath 1929/1973, and Stadler 2007).

    Neurath’s departing position was a critique of Carnap. In his classic work Der Logische Aufbau der Welt (1928) (known as the Aufbau and translated as The Logical Structure of the World), Carnap investigated the logical ‘construction’ (Russell’s term) of objects/concepts of inter-subjective knowledge out of the simplest starting point or basic types. To reconstruct empirical knowledge, Carnap explored an empiricist, or phenomenological, model in terms of the immediate experiential basis was quickly understood by fellow members of the Vienna Circle as manifesting three philosophical positions that structured the debate: reductionism, atomism and foundationalism.

    Reductionism took one set of terms to be fundamental or primitive; the rest would be logically connected to them.

    Atomism, especially in Neurath’s reading, was manifest semantically and syntactically: semantically, in the analyzability of a term; syntactically or structurally, in the elementary structure of protocols in terms of a single experiential term—‘red circle here now.’ It appeared further in the possibility of an individual testing relation of a theoretical statement to one of more experiential statements.

    Foundationalism, in the Cartesian tradition of a secure basis, took the beliefs in these terms held by the subject to be infallible, or not requiring verification, and the sole empirical source of epistemic warrant—or credibility—for all other beliefs. Descartes’s foundationalism is based on a priori knowledge; Carnap’s presentation of the empirical basis constitutes a more modest, naturalistic version (see also his 1932/1987).

    Neurath first confronted Carnap on yet another alleged feature of his system, namely, subjectivism. On this issue dovetailed Carnaps’ Kantian problematic of explicating the objectivity of empirical knowledge and Neurath’s materialism and social –and socialist– perspective on economic, political and epistemic matters. Neurath rejected Carnap’s proposals on the grounds that if the language and the system of statements that constitute scientific knowledge are intersubjective, then phenomenalist talk of immediate subjective, private experiences should have no place. More generally, Neurath offered a private language argument, featuring Robinson Crusoe, to the effect that languages are necessarily intersubjective:

    The universal jargon…is the same for the child and for the adult. It is the same for a Robinson Crusoe as for a human society. If Robinson wants to join what is in a protocol of yesterday with what is in his protocol today, that is, if he wants to make use of language at all, he must make use of the ‘intersubjective’ language. The Robinson of yesterday and the Robinson of today stand precisely in the same relation in which Robinson stands to Friday…In other words, every language as such is intersubjective. (Neurath 1932b/1983, 96)
    To replace Carnap’s phenomenalist language Neurath introduced in 1931 the language of physicalism (Neurath 1931/1983 and 1932a/1983). Physicalism is, for Neurath, the view that the unity, intelligibility and objectivity of science rest on using statements in a language of public things, events and processes in space and time —including behavior and physiological events, hence not necessarily in the technical terms of physical theory. Carnap promptly adopted a more technical version of physicalism requiring translatability of protocols to the language of physics (Carnap 1932/1934). While inspired by anti-metaphysical materialism, for Neurath this was a methodological and linguistic rule, and not an ontological thesis. The syntacticism mentioned above concerns the emphasis on spatio-temporal order or patterns. Neurath’s view could claim that language was itself was a physical process and could express its own spatio-temporal structure. This was also in line with his typographic concerns in logic and visual communication.

    That physicalism was to avoid metaphysical connotations can be seen further in that its linguistic nature was also central to its applications. Neurath insisted that statements can be compared only with statements, certainly not with some “reality”, nor with “things,” (Neurath 1931/1983, 53). Knowledge was a social matter of empirical control.

    Neurath responded with a new doctrine of protocol statements that considered their distinctive linguistic form, contents and methodological status (Neurath 1932b/1983). This doctrine was meant to explicate the idea of scientific evidence in the framework of empiricism, and it did so by specifying public conditions of evaluation and acceptance of a statement as empirical scientific evidence. In particular, Neurath intended the physicalist doctrine of protocol statements to circumvent the pitfalls of subjectivism, atomism, reductionism and foundationalism attributed to Carnap’s earlier discussion. It supported, instead, a holistic, anti-foundationalist, decisionistic, pragmatist, social view characterizing the scientific, empiricist attitude.

    One informal but paradigmatic example of a protocol was:

    Otto’s protocol at 3:17 o’clock: [Otto’s speech-thinking at 3:16 was: (at 3:15 o’clock there was a table in the room perceived by Otto)].
    Neurath offered examples over time featuring different numbers of parts, between two and four (on the debate around this issue, see Uebel 2007). Far from Carnap’s atomic sort of protocol statements, Neurath’s model manifested a distinctive complexity of terms and structure. The protocol contains a factual physicalist core in terms about the table and its location. It also contains the experiential term that provides the linguistic recording of the empirical character of protocols, that is, their experiential origin. Neurath was mindful to caution here that perception terms only admitted physicalistic meaning in terms, for instance, of behavior or physiological mechanisms of perception. It also contains the declarative level, marked with ‘Otto says’, which distinguishes the protocol as a linguistic statement. Finally, the other distinctive elements were the name of the protocolist and the times and locations of the experience and the reports, which provided an intersubjective, physicalist, public alternative to Carnap’s first-person, subjective ‘I see a red circle here now’.

    Unlike Carnap’s ideal of basic statement, whether protocol or physicalist, Neurath’s protocols were not ‘clean’, precise or pure in their terms. For Neurath physicalist language, and hence science in turn, is inseparable from ordinary language of any time and place. In particular, it is muddled with imprecise, unanalyzed, cluster-like terms (Ballungen) that appear especially in the protocols: the name of the protocolist, ‘seeing’, ‘microscope’, etc. They were often to be further analyzed into more precise terms or mathematical co-ordinations, but they often would not be eliminated. Even the empirical character of protocol statements could not be pure and primitive, as physicalism allowed the introduction of theoretical—non-perception—terms. Physicalism, and thus unified science, were based on a universal ‘jargon’.

    Neurath’s protocols didn’t have the atomic structure and the atomic testing role of Carnap’s. Their methodological role reflected Duhem’s holism: hypotheses are not tested individually; only clusters of statements confront empirical data. But their methodological value in the testing of other statements didn’t make them unrevisable. This is Neurath’s anti-foundationalism: Insofar as they were genuinely scientific statements, consistency with the spirit that opposed science to dogmatic speculation and, no less importantly, opposed naturalistic attention to actual practice, required that protocols too be testable. Physicalism challenges the epistemic authority of first-person private experience and enables the democratic socialization of empirical claims in the networks of scientific statements and collaborations.

    From this follows the so-called Neurath Principle: in the face of conflict between a protocol and theoretical statements, the cancellation of a protocol statement is a methodological possibility as well (Neurath 1932b/1983, Haller 1982). The role of indeterminacy in the protocol language points to a distinction between a special Neurath Principle and a general Neurath Principle (Cartwright et al. 1996, Cat 1995). In the former, and earlier, Neurath assumed a determinate logical relation of inconsistency. In the latter, subsequent version, the scope of relations between hypotheses and protocol statements extended to indeterminate relations such that the principle behind the epistemic status of protocol statements is simply grounded on the voluntaristic and conventionalist doctrine that ‘[a]ll content statements of science, and also their protocol statements that are used for verification, are selected on the basis of decisions and can be altered in principle’ (Neurath 1934/1983, 102).

    The complex structure of the explicitly laid out protocol would provide an explication and synoptic visual tool for differentiating and integrating explicitly relevant testing conditions: the intersubjective conditions of evaluation and acceptance of the record and its core data, or record of core factual information to enter the relevant scientific field of empirical research. The different conditions could guide the control of relevant data by laying out the conditions of their origin, validity and fallibility (was Otto hallucinating? were all the parts of the experimental instrument working reliably? etc.).

    Neurath’s dictum was meant to do justice to actual scientific practice and its normative standards with regards to the role of experimental data. It is up to the members of the scientific community to decide when a protocol can support or challenge a hypothesis, at last provisionally. Invalid protocols may change their status or be repurposed as data for historical or social studies of science (Uebel 2007 and Bentley 2023). What distinguishes the epistemic status of protocol sentences is not their foundational certainty (unlike for Schlick), but their stability as available and acceptable records over time and across projects and purposes. In this way they facilitate communication, cooperation and empirical inquiry.

    The method of testing failed to meet a certain standard and expectation of rationality: It could not be carried out in a logically precise, determinate and conclusive manner. expecting calculability, determinism, omniscience and certainty (Neurath 1913/1983, Neurath 1934/1983 and Cat 1995). By virtue of perception terms, protocol sentences could in fact provide certain stability in the permanence of information necessary for the generation of new expressions. But methodologically they could only bolster or shake our confidence. To acknowledge these limitations is a mark of proper rationality—which he opposed to pseudorationality.

    A loose coherentist view of warrant, acceptance and unification is the only logical criterion available: ‘a statement is called correct if it can be incorporated in this totality’ of ‘existing statements that have already been harmonized with each other’ (Neurath 1931/1984, 66). Reasons underdetermine our actions and thus pragmatic extra-logical factors are required to make decisions about what hypotheses to accept. Thinking requires provisional rules, or auxiliary motives, that fix a conclusion by decision (Neurath 1913/1983).

    Scientific rationality is situated, contextually constrained by, practical rationality. The construction of knowledge is constrained by historically, socially, methodologically and theoretically accepted claims and standards –as well as other possible factors he called extra-logical. They bear limited stability, and cannot be rebuilt on pure, secure, infallible empirical foundations. This is the anti-Cartesian naturalism, non-foundationalism, fallibilism and holism of Neurath’s social model. This is also the basis for its corresponding decisonistic, conventionalist, constructivist normativity (Uebel 1996 and 2007 and Cartwright et al. 1996). Without the norms and conventions self-issued within a community, there is no possibility of rationality or objectivity of knowledge. Neurath captured the main features of his doctrine of scientific knowledge in the image of a boat:

    There is no way to establish fully secured, neat protocol statements as starting points of the sciences. There is no tabula rasa. We are like sailors who have to rebuild their ship on the open sea, without ever being able to dismantle it in dry-dock and reconstruct it from its best components. Only metaphysics can disappear without a trace. Imprecise ‘verbal clusters’ [Ballungen] are somehow always part of the ship. If imprecision is diminished at one place, it may well re-appear at another place to a stronger degree. (Neurath 1932b/1983, 92)
    Just like Neurath debated Carnap, he also entered an acrimonious debate with Popper and Schlick. By 1934, the year of the completion of his Logic of Scientific Discovery (Logik der Forschung), Popper had adopted an approach to scientific knowledge based on the logic of method, not on meaning, so that any talk of individual experience would have no linguistic expres​sion(Popper 1935/1951). He was concerned with the post-Kantian problematic of the rational objective validity of scientific knowledge claims.

    Instead of protocols, Popper proposed to speak about basic statements—a term more attuned to their logical and functional role. They are basic relative to a theory under test. Their empirical character would invisibly reside in the requirement that basic statements be singular existential ones describing material objects in space and time—much like Neurath’s physicalism—which would be observable, in a further unspecified logical not psychological sense. Their components would not themselves be purely empirical terms since many would be understood in terms of dispositional properties, which, in turn, involved reference to law-like generalizations. But their ‘basic’ role was methodological ‘with no direct function of demarcation from metaphysics in terms of meaning, sense or cognitive significance’ and only provisional. They would be brought to methodological use for the purpose of falsifying theories and hypotheses ‘individually and conclusively’ only once they were conventionally and communally accepted by decision in order to stop infinite regress and further theoretical research.

    But such acceptance, much as in Neurath’s model, could be in principle revoked. It is a contingent fact that scientists will stop at easily testable statements simply because it will be easier to reach an agreement. It is important that basic statements satisfy explicit conditions of testability or else they could not be rightful part of science. Popper could offer no rational theory of their acceptance on pain of having to have recourse to theories of psychology of perception and thereby weakening his normative criterion of demarcation. In his view, his method, unlike Neurath’s, didn’t lead to either arbitrariness or dogmatism or the abandonment of empiricism. As he had argued against Spengler in 1921, historical contingency provides the rich constraints that establish communities and communication and the possibility of knowledge and, in this holistic form, preclude radical relativism in practice; in historically situated practice, inherited or constructed stable Archimedean points always come into place; there is no tabula rasa (Neurath 1921/1973). Neurath rejected Popper’s approach for its stealth empiricism and its pseudorationalism: its misplaced emphasis on and faith in the normative uniqueness, precision and conclusiveness of a logical method—at the expense of its own limitations and pragmatic character (Zolo 1989, Cat 1995, Hacohen 2000).

    Finally, the most radical empiricist attitude toward protocol sentences within the Vienna Circle came from Schlick. Schlick endorsed, following Hilbert, a formal, structural notion of communicable, objective knowledge and meaning as well as a correspondence theory of truth. His realism opposed Neurath’s coherentism, and also the pragmatism and conventionalism of Carnap’s Principle of Tolerance in logical matters, as well as his Thesis of Metalogic. But like Carnap’s latter thesis and his syntactic approach of 1934, Schlick was concerned with both the Cartesian ideal of foundational certainty and Wittgenstein’s metalinguistic problem of how language represents the reality it is about; such relation could only be shown, not said. In 1934 Schlick proposed to treat the claims motivating protocol statements, left by Neurath with the status of little more than mere hypotheses, as key to the foundation of knowledge. They would be physicalistic statements that, albeit being fallible, could be subjectively linked to statements about immediate private experiences of reality such as ‘blue here now’ he called affirmations (Konstatierungen) (Schlick 1934).

    Affirmations carried certainty and elucidated what could be showed but not said, they provided the elusive confrontation or correspondence between theoretical propositions and facts of reality. In this sense they afforded, according to Schlick, the fixed starting points and foundation of all knowledge. But the foundation raised a psychological and semantic problem about the longer-term acceptance of a protocol. Affirmations, as acts of verification or giving meaning, lacked logical inferential force; in Schlick’s words, they ‘do not occur within science itself, and can neither be derived from scientific propositions, nor the latter from them’ (Schlick 1934, 95). Schlick’s empiricism regarding the role of protocol sentences suggests but does not support strong epistemological foundationalism. Schlick’s occasional references to a correspondence theory of truth were just as unacceptable and were felt to be even more of a philosophical betrayal within the framework of empiricism. Predictably, Neurath rejected Schlick’s doctrines as metaphysical, manifesting the pseudorationalist attitude (Neurath 1934/1983).



    _________________
    « La question n’est pas de constater que les gens vivent plus ou moins pauvrement, mais toujours d’une manière qui leur échappe. » -Guy Debord, Critique de la séparation (1961).

    « Rien de grand ne s’est jamais accompli dans le monde sans passion. » -Hegel, La Raison dans l'Histoire.

    « Mais parfois le plus clair regard aime aussi l’ombre. » -Friedrich Hölderlin, "Pain et Vin".

    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Admin


    Messages : 20709
    Date d'inscription : 12/08/2013
    Localisation : France

    Otto Neurath Empty Re: Otto Neurath

    Message par Johnathan R. Razorback Mer 20 Mar - 13:14



    "4. Unity of Science and the Encyclopedia Model
    Neurath’s concern with unity in the sciences has multiple sources and served different kinds of purposes; his proposals also had different forms and played different roles. In the contect of logical empiricism we may identify at least five: prediction, acceptance, cooperation, demarcation and metascience (or scientific philosophy).

    Early in his intellectual life, at the turn of the twentieth century, Neurath was acquainted with at least four recent images and projects of unification of the sciences: (1) The scholastic (Llull) and rationalist (Leibniz) tradition of an ideal universal language and calculus of reasoning; (2) the Neo-Kantians and others’ emphasis on the distinction between the Naturwissenschaften and the Geisteswissenschaften; (3) Wundt’s comprehensive logical viewpoints associated with different sciences, or perspectival monism; and (4) the Monist movement more generally, with figures such as Ernst Haeckel and Wilhelm Ostwald that included the project of energetics, with Mach’s related bio-economic, neutral monism of elementary sensations.

    By 1910, Neurath had engaged four connected debates: (1) The debate over the Neo-Kantian divide between natural and human, or cultural, sciences; (2) the debate over the distinctive role of value judgment in the social sciences; (3) the debate over the scope and validity of concepts, laws and methods in economics; and (4) the debate over the possibility of history as a positive science.

    In the face of alternatives, he often sought synthetic positions, e.g., integrating the application of empirical inductive methods and theoretical deductive methods in the social sciences by the empirical standards of the natural sciences and within a historical perspective that explored and classified possible cases, past, present and future. In his programmatic theory of the social sciences of 1910 –a review of Wundt’s theory of the sciences– he declared: ‘True science consists in systematically examining all possible cases.’ (Neurath 2004, 278)

    He also argued for unity within a science and unity of the different individual sciences. He called it cooperative division of labor instead of specialized separation of labor (Neurath 2004, 265–288). The former is guided by general perspectives providing connecting links between individual sciences (he cited Llull and Leibniz as early relevant examples of the project of universal knowledge). Those links operate as auxiliary hypotheses and a better sense for what might be accepted and rejected –echoing and extending Duhem’s holistic methodological model of testing. Cooperation between generalist and specialized research, he declared, will supplement and correct each other; and collaborative efforts towards seeking connections from all specialized work will bring to specialized components significance in organization rather than chaos (Neurath 2004, 287).

    Unity became central to the Vienna Circle’s project. And Neurath made sure of it. In the Vienna Circle’s manifesto (Carnap et al., 1929) and elsewhere, Neurath urged and welcomed a scientistic turn in philosophy he labelled the scientific world-conception. Beyond the intellectual value, he added, ‘the scientific world-conception serves life and life receives it’ (Carnap, Hahn and Neurath 1929/1973, 306, orig. ital.). Here the project of logical empiricism gets its Viennese Enlightenment dimension, with the old reforming, constructive and universalist ambitions, but with new and revised ideas and ideals of society, science and rationality (Uebel 1998). Neurath continued to maintain the view that, as predictive tools, all sciences are ‘aids to creative life’ (Neurath 1931/1973, 319), alongside his view of the complexity of life, e.g., the earthly plane of the empirical world that includes the human. It cannot surprise, then, that in this new transformative joint philosophical-social project he would urge that ‘the goal ahead is unified science’ (Carnap et al. 1929/1973, 306, orig. ital.). Like science itself, unified science straddles any divide between theory and action, the world of physical objects and the world of social objectives, past and future, empirical reality and human realization. It is unity of science at the point of action (Cartwright et al 1991, Cartwright et al. 1996 and O’Neill 2003). Not just philosophy; also science at the point of action is unified science.

    The goal of science –and the key to its practical application–, he repeated, was empirical prediction. The focus on language placed unity of language at the center of unification. Physicalism and its universal jargon were, as mentioned above, precisely the key to achieving the social and intellectual goals of the scientific world-conception and logical empiricism. Physicalism also provided a unification of the natural and human sciences.

    In addition, and based on an available connecting language for the sciences, Neurath introduced the holistic argument for unification from the complexity of life. It generalized, again, Duhem’s holistic argument about prediction and testing; and he illustrated it with the example of a forest fire:

    Certainly, different kinds of laws can be distinguished from each other: for example, chemical, biological or sociological laws; however, it can not be said of a prediction of a concrete individual process that it depend on one definite kind of law only. For example, whether a forest will burn down at a certain location on earth depends as much on the weather as on whether human intervention takes place or not. This intervention, however, can only be predicted if one knows the laws of human behaviour. That is, under certain circumstances, it must be possible to connect all kinds of laws with each other. Therefore all laws, whether chemical, climatological or sociological, must be conceived as parts of a system, namely of unified science. (Neurath 1931/1983, 59, orig. itals.)
    Laws of one kind may apply nicely to systems, phenomena or events purely of one kind, but such things are not concrete individuals in the real world. We may think of them as useful models or abstractions; reality behaves more like them only in controlled settings, the outcome of engineering, of planned design and construction, that is, the materialized form of abstraction. Idealizations, like ideal types, dangerously assume real separability between properties (Neurath 1941/1983, 225). In this sense, necessary experimentation for the purpose of prediction and testing that control is key to observation and in turn observation controls theory. In general, from that point of view, exactness and scope requires the possibility of composing models, laws and sciences of different kinds. Unity demands multiple levels of integration and social cooperation.

    The argument from holism would also serves th purpose of empiricist demarcation against metaphysics: since metaphysical terms and metaphysicians divide, whereas scientific terms and scientists unite. Recall his practical standard of demarcation by integration mentioned above. Metaphysical claims are uncontrollble and isolated.

    The boat images further illustrated Neurath’s aim of unity, within its proper epistemological framework: as a historically situated, non-foundational and collective enterprise. Science is a model and a resource for society and society is in turn a model and resource for science.

    In the context of the rise of logical empiricism, Neurath’s campaign in support of the unity of science project was intellectual and practical. It relied on rhetorical appeals to references to historical precedents from such as Leibniz and L’Encyclopédie (see SCIENTIFIC UNITY) as well as a planned movement that involved a variety of institutions –Vienna Circle, Institute of Unified Science–, events –International Congresses for the Unity of Science– and publications –International Encyclopedia of Unified Science– (Neurath 1937a/1983, Reisch 1994, Symons et al. 2011).

    What is the proposed model of unity? What is the opposed alternative? Despite popular approaches suggesting a hierarchical, or pyramidal, structure, which he associated with, among others, Comte, Ostwald and then Carnap (in the Aufbau and in his subsequent doctrine of physicalism), Neurath opposed the ideal of ‘pyramidism’ and a ‘system-model’: an axiomatic, precisely and deductively closed and complete hierarchy of conceptually pure, distinct and fixed sciences. He also dismissed the idea of ONE method and ONE ideal language, for instance, mathematics or physics, followed by all the other sciences (Neurath 1936/1983 and Neurath 1937b/1983). Since 1910 Neurath’s approach to the issue was thoroughly antireductionist: cognitively, logically and pragmatically. Each science would fail to deal with the connections to others (Neurath 1910/2004). In particular, electron talk, Neurath insisted, is irrelevant to understanding and predicting the complex behavior of social groups. He had identified hierarchical reductionism across disciplines in Carnap’s Aufbau. It is worth noting that Neurath’s encyclopedic disciplinary anti-reductionism is not in conflict with the conceptual reductionist character of his physicalism as a model of empiricism. In fact, this anti-reductionism may be thought the nomological part of the doctrine of physicalism, alongside its epistemological and metalinguistic elements (Uebel 2004).

    The imperative of unity required that ‘it must be possible to connect each law with every other law under certain circumstances, in order to obtain new formulations’ (Neurath 1931/1983, 59). Instead of the system-model, he proposed a weaker, dynamical and local model of integration he called the ‘encyclopedia-model’: a more or less coherent totality of scientific statements at a given time, in flux, incomplete, with linguistic imprecisions and logical indeterminacy and gaps, unified linguistically by the universal jargon of physicalist language (not Carnap’s physicalism)—a mixture of ‘cluster’ and ‘formula’—, the cooperative and empiricist spirit, and the acceptance of a number of methods or techniques (probability, statistics, etc), all providing ‘cross-connections’ (Neurath 1936/1983, 145–158 and 213–229).

    The evolution of the sciences could be said to proceed from encyclopedias to encyclopedias (a model weaker and more pluralistic than those based on Kuhn’s paradigms and Foucault’s epistèmes, but closer to Carnap’s later notion of linguistic frameworks; from this perspective, it seems less paradoxical that Carnap published Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions in the last volume of the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science). Neurath spoke of a ‘mosaic’, an ‘aggregation’, an interdisciplinary ‘orchestration’ of the sciences as ‘systematisation from below’ rather than a ‘system from above’, especially, after World War II, carefully excluding any form of ‘authoritative integration’, even favoring ‘cooperation in fruitful discussion’ to a socialist, Nazi or totalitarian-sounding talk of a ‘programme’ (Neurath 1936/1983 and Neurath 1946/1983, 230–242). Correspondingly, his later political writings emphasized internationalism, democracy and plurality of institutional loyalties.

    5. Philosophy of psychology, education, and the social sciences
    5.1 Philosophy of psychology
    Neurath’s attention to psychology was part of new disciplinary landscape that connected and differentiated him from other thinkers. Vienna became an international capital of psychological research while logical empiricism started to develop a scientific epistemology and an epistemology of science. Freud’s psychoanalysis was more popular than J.B. Watson’s American behaviorism and Gestalt psychology was dominant neither in psychology nor in scientific philosophy. In the Vienna Circle’s manifesto, the official programmatic position was weariness and rejection of much contemporary psychological language. It was considered plagued with conceptual imprecision, logical inconsistency and, most fatally, meaningless, untestable metaphysical elements. The project’s emphasis on perception led to adopting behaviorist psychology as the natural intellectual ally consistent with the Circle’s scientific world-conception (Carnap, Hahn and Neurath 1929/1973, 314-5, Hardcastle 2007).

    Like Kant, Popper was interested in a transcendental and regulative philosophy, and, more so than Kant, he hailed science as the paradigm of intellectual activity. In 1928 Popper finished his doctoral dissertation, ‘On the Methodological Problem of Cognitive Psychology’. Popper set out to understand the relations between logic, biology and psychology in the production of knowledge and thereby to outline the methodological preconditions of cognitive psychology. Two alternative views of psychology were available to Popper through two doctoral examiners, Karl Bühler and Moritz Schlick.

    Schlick represented Gestalt theory as psychology within the reductive framework of physicalism, that is, rejecting the existence of autonomous entities, laws and methods of psychology. Bühler’s career was central to Austrian psychology and to socialist Red Vienna culture. With Ostwald Külpe in Würtzburg he had engaged in empirical research on thought processes—contra Wundt’s atomistic psychology-; they paid special attention to imageless thought and the importance of language. In 1912 Bühler had originally contributed to Gestalt psychology with the discussion of simple Gestalt forms involved in the perception of proportions of geometrical figures and ended concentrating on his cognitive phenomenon of the ‘aha experience’, a sudden insight in problem solving.

    In Vienna, Otto Glöckel, founder of the world-renowned Vienna School Reform movement and president of the Vienna School Board, offered to fund for the Bühler and his child-pscyhology wife a psychological laboratory. Child psychology and education were seen central to the socialsit project of creating a New Man. His interest in language and philosophy brought him closer to Schlick (Wittgenstein’s sister Margaret organized social occasions for Wittgenstein, the Bühlers and the Schlicks to meet) and he encouraged his students to attend Vienna Circle seminars (Egon Brunswick, Elsa Frankel, Marie Jahoda, Paul Lazersfeld, Rudolf Ekstein and Edith Weisskopf). In the wake of earlier discussions of crises in physics and mathematics, in 1927 he published Die Krise der Psychologie (The Crisis of Psychology). In the book, Bühler argued that the problem of explaining the social significance of language showed that psychology has lost the complexity and richness required to synthesize three levels of psychology: experience, behavior and intellectual structure (Bühler 1927, Hacohen 2000 and Humphrey 1951). A framework was needed for unifying the different narrow ‘schools’ of psychology: Behaviorism, Gestalt theory, psychoanalysis, associationism, and humanistic psychology. They were deficient in their narrow domain of application. The unity of psychology demanded methodological pluralism at the point of cooperation.

    Initially Popper had tied the scientific status of psychology to the notion that induction is the empirical method of the natural sciences and wrote on the inductive basis of pedagogy (ter Hark 2002, and Gattei 2004, 453). In his second thesis, on the method of cognitive psychology, Popper declared that psychology was better off autonomous, discovering empirically new laws and phenomena that only subsequently might or might not prove reducible to a material interpretation. Popper critiqued Gestalt psychology by analogy with Bühler’s problem regarding language: Gestalt psychology was too narrow to establish the conditions of possibility of cognitive psychology and the logic of intellectual structures. He was further interested in the Viennese Otto Selz’s holistic, functional notion of ‘total task’, based on a psychological mechanism of trial and error (this notion would later inspire not only Popper’s pedagogy, but elements of his scientific methodology of hypotheses and falsification, conjectures and refutations).

    In the Aufbau Carnap associated Watson’s behaviorism with a physicalist basis for a construction system, whereas Gestalt psychology was better suited to reflect the origin of the concepts in our system of knowledge –it was also better than Mach’s atomism of sensations– (Carnap 1928 and 1932). Here Carnap was seeking to accommodate the epistemic value of individual experience while preserving the objective form of scientific knowledge (Friedman 1999). Experience contributed a complex holistic stream—a ‘true’, ‘organic’ whole—out of which the elementary empirical concepts must be abstracted, by the process he called quasi-analysis.

    Like Wittgenstein and Popper, Neurath was interested in education and cognitive psychology (especially during the Red Vienna period; and, like Popper, also in connection with socialist goals). Neurath’s crusade for unified science against speculative metaphysics prompted him in 1931 to propose the unified framework of physicalism for all acceptable scientific concepts, statements and theories. As mentioned above, it was a materialist view that knowledge (science) can speak only of observable events, things and processes in space and time. This normative view aimed to unify the natural and the human sciences, yet it did not require any reduction to physics.

    Neurath rejected, accordingly, the language of the unconscious and the ego, subjective mental states devoid of material (physiological), perceptual, or operational correlates. All events and processes, all perceptual, speech and thought terms involved in the production of empirical data were to be taken physicalistically, e.g., as descriptions of spatio-temporal structures involving behavior or bodily—anatomical and physiological- changes under given observed conditions (Neurath 1931/1983, 55).

    Neurath’s goal was also to achieve a unity of acceptable empirical formulations in psychology. The only acceptable psychological positions were the kinds of behaviorism championed by J.B. Watson, E.C. Tolman, and F.B. Skinner and physiological theories (Neurath 1931a/1983, 50; 1931b/1983, 55; 1932a/1983, 63, 67, and 73). Yet he also drew some distance between physicalism and behaviorism by declaring the latter both too narrow and too broad, and containing non-physicalist notions (Neurath 1936/1983, 164). He came to distinguish behaviorism, in this narrow sense, from ‘behavioristics’, the emphasis on perceptual considerations of behavior within the framework of physicalism (Neurath 1933/1987, 13). Neurath mentioned Gestalt theory as one of the schools of psychology alongside behaviorism and psychoanalysis disrupting the unity of psychology as a discipline (implicitly echoing Bühler’s earlier lamentations; Neurath 1937/1983, 172–3, and 1933/1987, 15), but he did not mention Gestalt as an example of scientific psychology (on this point claims in Cat 2005 require qualification). He merely pointed to the promise of its empirical contributions to scientific behaviorism with a rejection of its talk of holistic properties as metaphysical danglers (Neurath 1933/1987, 17–Cool.

    5.2 Philosophy of education
    As mentioned above, psychology and pedagogy were inseparable in Vienna’s intellectual, scientific and political culture of the 1920s. Glöckel’s school reform movement of 1922 onwards advocated empirical research in pedagogy, it separated school from church and promoted social equality. Child welfare became a central concern and, for intellectual and or political reasons, attracted the pedagogical interest of Popper, Wittgenstein and Neurath (on Popper see Hacohen 2002; Wittgenstein see Bartley 1974 and Peters 2001). In their pedagogical activities one can find the roots of some of their epistemological views. Popper and Wittgenstein became school-teachers and Wittgenstein even published in 1925 a spelling dictionary, Wörterbuch für Volksschullen.

    Lili Roubiczek, a student of Maria Montessori in London and Karl Bühler in Vienna established a Montessori school in 1923 and soon Montessori ideas attracted educators and psychologists alike (from Charlotte Bühler to Anna Freud) (Kramer 1988). Montessori stressed the idea of the child’s capacity for active self-directed learning through sensory and motor interaction with the environment with guidance and error-correcting feedback. Gestalt psychologists, psychoanalysts and others defended similarly active models of the child’s mind. Popper’s awareness of Montessori methods in the 1920s stemmed from several opportunities: his pedagogical training, his friendship with a carpenter who made toys for a Montessori orphanage and turned him to cabinet-making and the Montessori-inspired ‘Socratic method’ of his admired Kantian critical philosopher Leonard Nelson (Hacohen 2000, 90 and 122).

    Neurath’s views on education, as did his scientific epistemology, integrated social, political, scientific and empiricist elements in a mutually reinforcing manner. The most influential example and outcome of his views were the development and application of the ISOTYPE method of visual education (See the supplementary document Visual Education.).

    For Neurath, education involves argument and discussion. It is in this sense dialogical. The term ‘argument’ was used by Neurath broadly, to include the case or point being made and communicated, both senses of demonstration. Neurath wrote that to argue requires one to distinguish between essentials and incidentals (Neurath 1945/1973, 239). So, a visual argument is ‘a combination of verbal and visual aids leading to the essentials’ (ibid., 240).

    Under the aegis of the values of social cooperation, neutrality and universality that characterized his thinking, Neurath sought a universal medium for the communication of knowledge that combined visual perception and scientific information. Science is ‘the typical species of arguing which human beings of all nations, rich and poor, have in common’ (ibid., 229). The choice of the visual, later linked to his empiricism, was also prompted by models of education and interest in children. Quoting from the Victorian self-improvement author Samuel Smiles, he declared that ‘all persons are more or less apt to learn through the eyes rather than the ear… especially the case in early youth, when the eye is the chief inlet of knowledge’ (Neurath 1946, 100). This approach was consistent with Montessori’s and other contemporary educational theories as well as with typical approaches to science education. He repeatedly pointed to another Victorian hero of his, Britain’s foremost experimental scientist and popular science educator, Michael Faraday, and his Course of Six Lectures on the Chemical History of a Candle (1861), which was intended primarily for children. Given the importance he placed on scientific information, also socially, the main challenge he routinely took up became the concretization of abstract information, especially the visual communication of statistical information. In that regard, he also believed that visual education provided a unifying framework that bridged the gap between science and the humanities (Neurath 1945/1973, 234).

    Education requires simplification, that is, the empiricist notion of abstraction in the face of the complexity of facts. Teaching requires knowing what to leave out, what counts as superfluous detail and accuracy: ‘he who knows best what to omit is the best teacher’ and so ‘to remember simplified pictures is better than to forget accurate figures’ (Neurath 1933/1973, 220 and 1945a, 440). The graphic, visual counterpart of this point constitutes the basis for his design of ISOTYPE icons, by analogy with the method of silhouettes, so popular in Austrian art, as a form of visual abstraction for the communication of information about types or general concepts. The approach was consistent with the empiricist anti-metaphysical spirit and Bauhaus and modernist aesthetics of the rejection of ornament famously advocated by the Viennese architect Adolf Loos in Ornament and Crime (1908) also echoed by Neurath in 1926: ‘the time of ornaments is over’ (recounted by Ernst Niekisch in Neurath 1973, 22).

    In line with the Viennese School Reform movement led by Glöckel and his own scientific attitude, he adopted an scientific approach to visual education: by applying accepted recent ideas from empirical disciplines such as developmental psychology, anthropology, art history, even ideas by his Encyclopedia co-editor Charles Morris in his Foundations of a Theory of Signs (Morris 1938); and by testing the end-products, albeit with different degrees of rigor (see the supplementary document on Visual Education).

    Neurath was aware of the values and limitations of the elements of visual education (see below), and admitted the diversity of tools and values with the same kind of pluralism, holism and pragmatism he adopted in his economic theory and more general scientific epistemology: each educational media had educational characteristics of each own that are incomparable and non-additive, cannot be ranked and serve different purposes (Neurath 1944, 56, Neurath 1945/1973, 238 and Neurath 1946, 99).

    The sensual dimension of education is part of the larger goal of humanization: the elimination of secret knowledge and exclusive communities. Education involves the language of daily life and the avoidance of unnecessary technical terms, and thereby enables organized humanity, including international cooperation (Neurath 1945/1973, 231).

    More intellectually, education involves comparison (Neurath 1945/1973, 238). But the comparative analysis, which Hume made a staple of empiricist methodology, does not exhaust the gamut of intellectual values. The exploration of incomparable or alternative possibilities is a key cognitive goal of education that was to make the other specific practices possible (logically and psychologically). He called this meditation: besides handing out knowledge, education involves a transfer of criticism, a meditative mood and atmosphere, and the ability to consider matter under discussion from all sides (possible and actual perspectives within the pluralistic attitude) (ibid., 233). Again, this aspect of his philosophy of education featured also in his thinking on economic and social theory, practical rationality and scientific method.

    Education should discourage narrow specialization (recall his early arguments for the unification of the sciences). Since the holistic and synthetic model of socialization, epistemology and science requires the consideration of alternative perspectives and the integration of different kinds of knowledge. Neurath praised the Danish pedagogical model of university education, a Philosophy Faculty in the medieval comprehensive, universalist spirit of the scholastic meaning of ‘university’. In the setting of one of the Congresses of the Unity of Science Movement, he praised the requirement at University of Copenhagen of mandatory science and philosophy courses for students of all specialties, and Joerg Joergensen’s lectures on scientific thinking based on historical explanation and logical reasoning (Neurath 1938).

    Education depends on intellectual ethos and social values as well. Education includes what he called also the habits of scientific attitude: habits of ‘sincerity of research and integrity of arguing’ (Neurath 1946/1973, 233). Education involves also tolerance: the transfer of tradition is a preference within one community, not an expression of an absolute higher point of view above other communities, also a preference among others within that community independent of that tradition (ibid., 229). It is worth noting that Neurath, and later his wife Anna Schapire, had been inspired very early on by the social views on education and feminism of the Swedish social reformer and educator Ellen Key (see Sandner 2014).

    The social dimension was a recurring theme even though with changing connotations or emphasis, from post-WWI socialism to post-WWII internationalism. Public education was dependent on an institutional basis consisting of a number of institutions: schools, museums and other places holding public exhibitions, and periodicals (Neurath 1931/1973, 222). Neurath was director of the Social and Economic Museum in Vienna from 1924 until 1934. Not coincidently, his cousin Waldemar Kaempffert planned and proceeded along lines similar to Neurath’s during his tenure as director of the Museum for Science and Industry of Chicago from 1928 until 1931.

    The social dimension extended to groups, generations and nations related by education as the process of group transfer of traditions: ‘Education may be regarded as the transfer of certain traditions in a more or less systematized way, from one person to another person, from one group of persons to another group, particularly from one generation to the next. It is also the transfer of tradition from one nation to another’ (Neurath 1945/1973, 228).

    It also extended to political arrangements, from socialism and democracy to ideals of international cooperation. The earlier views emphasized the socialist significance of education as condition of democracy in the form of informed participation and of cooperation, since ‘successful collaboration is possible only when those who act fix on one possibility, whether by agreement or by propaganda’ (Neurath 1928/1973, 293). Education as spreading of knowledge is required for everyone involved in taking common decisions and hence for the working of democracy (Neurath 1945/1973, 230). Democratic society, Neurath concluded, requires a common language (ibid., 247). Post-WWII internationalism became a motivation for visual education (ibid., 234, 247). The goals of a common language without common laws and a common language for common knowledge and cooperation rendered visual language a socio-political tool, the non-dictatorial basis for a potential human brotherhood (ibid., 248). In both contexts, Neurath offered a criticism of elitist individualistic teaching with a contrast between Anglo-Saxon education methods linked to empiricism and utilitarianism and Nazi education linked to German romanticism and transcendentalism (Neurath 1945b, 370–1).

    The social and political valence of education provided the framework for linking education to social structures such as entrenched institutions, techniques and habits involving advertising and entertainment that supported the relevant cognitive models such as visual media: ‘Modern man is conditioned by the cinema and a wealth of illustrations. He gets much of his knowledge during leisure hours in the most pleasing way through his eyes. If one wants to spread social knowledge, one should use means similar to modern advertisement’ (Neurath 1925/1973, 214). In the latter context, Neurath stressed the superiority of visual education to verbal education as the basis for international or general education: ‘words divide, pictures unite’ (Neurath 1931/1973, 217).

    5.3 Philosophy of the social sciences
    As in the case of philosophy of psychology, Neurath intended his theory of the social sciences to be a bridge between the natural and the human sciences and an exmplary application of the logical empiricist framework. Philosophy was now the reflexive perspective of unified science and it was constituted by two meta-theoretical approaches to science: logical analysis and empirical theory, that is, the ‘logic of science’—emphasized by Carnap— and the ‘behavioristics of science’—emphasized by Neurath.

    The application of physicalism encompassed psychology, history, economics, anthropology and sociology without reducing them to physics. Social sciences are scientific within the framework of physicalism, namely, insofar as they describe concrete spatially and temporally ordered events and processes and make predictions about them (Neurath 1931b/1973, 325). According to Neurath, social behavior is itself a complex and its prediction requires that sociology incorporate various sources such as history, ethics, jurisprudence, economics, ethnography, etc. (ibid., 328). One example was Marx’s study of capital. For Neurath it was important first and foremost as an instance of empirical research that brings together history and economics, and the most complete case of physicalist sociology (ibid., 349). Sociology is a synthetic effort part of in turn a larger synthetic effort that is unified science, the set of all connectible languages and laws required to describe and predict order. The synthetic dimension is inseparable from the empirical one: It is the formal, linguistic and conceptual, expression of the totalistic, holist approach required by the conception of empirical reality as a complex, including the phenomena of ‘concrete ways of life’.

    The alliance between unity and empiricism, or physicalism, is thrown into further relief by contrast with the post-Diltheyan German sociology of Windelband, Rickert, Sombart and Weber. They distinguished between the natural and the social sciences and, as distinctive feature of the latter, in Weber’s sociology there appear non-scientific, non-behavioristic entities and activities such as the spirit of the age (Zeitgeist), and empathy or understanding, poetic activity that grounds what he calls ‘Verstehende sociology’ (ibid., 353). Neurath’s was willing to accept the use of some such concepts provided they could be given a physicalistic meaning (Uebel 2004 and 2019).

    Neurath emphasized attention to individuals and groups, individuated in terms of stimulus/response interrelationship and clusters of shared customs and habits, and, for instance, the transfer of such habits or traditions (ibid., 371), which is how he defined education (see above). Linked to Mach’s bio-economic ideas, Neurath’s sociology relied on biological elements.

    The empirical conceptualization of the social units is Gestalt-like and holistic, like the silhouettes, patterns or profiles of total life plans: ‘Peoples, states, age groups, religious communities, all are complexes built up of single individuals. Such composite groups have certain interconnections which are ruled by laws, and they have a definite ‘physiognomy’. The separate features of these complexes are not independent of each other but are related’ (ibid., 387). Decisions and predictions, as in the case of social planning, often involved the ‘comparison of total complexes’ (ibid.).

    Citing Mill, Neurath noted that empiricism brings the natural and the social sciences together, but so do some of its limits. The markers of empirical science are the practices of observation, experimentation and prediction. Laws are merely vehicles for taking us from the concrete and unique to the concrete and unique, whether in biology or history. Sociology is like geology and biology in that the possibility of many experiments is prevented by certain constraints of ethical values or scale (ibid., 365).

    Predictability is characterized by nine conditions.

    (1) It is based on the availability of generalizations about groups and (2) of stable conditions, or control, and for a limited period. Control is a key notion that connects empiricism and engineering, mechanical and social. Neurath didn’t think that laws of physics, for instance, are in that sense more universal or unconditioned: ‘Mariotte’s law in physics holds only within certain limits’ (ibid., 331).

    (3) Correlations on which predictions are based are the product of induction, and inductive conclusions, in sociology as elsewhere, are based on a decision (Neurath 1931b/1973, 407).

    (4) Moreover, sociology, like the natural sciences, often has recourse to information, including laws, from other disciplines, in a local synthetic effort of predictive value (ibid., 364).

    (5) Holism prevents sociology from the ‘ideal forecast’ associated with the fiction of the Laplacean mind and the availability of molecular descriptions of individuals free from instabilities (in a symposium on Pasqual Jordan’s quantum mechanics, Neurath addressed the new perspective from quantum mechanics on the problem of free will and its conflict with the determinism (causality) of natural laws as riddled with metaphysics (Neurath 1935)). One may not expect, however, that aggregations or complexes will be always more predictable than individuals, since the evolution of the complex might depend on the interaction with individuals and the environment in a way affected by chance. Instead, it has to make do with ‘rough facts of a complex character’ (ibid., 405) in a ‘system of entangled habits’ (ibid., 371 and 374), and most social types of behavior in a group are not ‘autonomously computable’ and have to be regarded as ‘parts of the complex that is being investigated at the time’, considering ‘the whole of life’ of the group, since each ‘historical period = non-analysed complex of conditions’ (Neurath 1932a/1983, 76 and 85); he would subsequently speak of aggregations (Neurath 1944a). Any resulting prediction or explanation (retrodiction) of individual behavior is an approximation to a ‘world history without names.’

    (6) A linguistic implication is that empiricism in general and the social sciences in particular are dependent on non-univocal, indistinct terms—‘a “clot” (German Ballung, French grégat)’—, in both protocol statements (see above) and theories insofar as they are sensitive to cultural phenomena and historically inherited concepts that cannot be usefully replaced with precise technical terms of the ‘modern international folklore’ (Neurath 1944a, 5–7, 18).

    (7) The ‘multivocality’ of the relation between phenomena and theoretical interpretations is more pervasive than the sort of pluralism Duhem noted in physics, and lead Neurath to speak of ‘pluri-items’ (ibid., 14).

    (Cool Certain phenomena or entities such as inventions can only be predicted provided one has also the means to create them (Neurath 1931b/1973, 405); this insight is typically attributed to the critic of Neurath Popper, who published it much later (Uebel 2004).

    (9) Sociological predictions are co-determinants in the occurrence of the predicted event, for instance a position in the stock market or a political revolution (ibid., 405); the prediction may have a reinforcing or a preventive character (he wrote about self-fulfilling prophecies as early as 1921, in his polemic against Spengler; Neurath 1921). Theory becomes part of practice; scientist becomes part of the social scene (ibid., 406; Uebel 2004).

    A related issue is Max Weber’s issue of value-freedom, and objectivity, in the social sciences. Neurath noted, with Weber, that all sciences are based on values that determine the choice of relevant aspects, phenomena, quantities, etc. This is not just consistent with, but an implication of his voluntarism and his ‘rationalism’. He insisted on scientists exploring and. proposing technical solutions to social problems that eventually required non-technical social or political choices. Value-free methods are central, with qualifications, to scientific practice. The formulation of a question or the choice of a quantity might be value-dependent but their respective answer or measurement will not be so in the same sense (ibid., 364–5). Neurath formulated the same idea in terms of theory-dependence: the putting right questions and making the right observations require a ‘meta-concept’ or an ‘approximate theory’ (ibid., 388–89).

    In spite of these caveats, the value of the social sciences remains attached to the value of empirical knowledge and the scientific attitude in the social roots of our life: ‘Even where sociologists cannot make predictions, they may provide men of action or meditation with empiricist material. (…) We argue differently and act differently when we know the material provided by the social sciences. (…) altering our scientific language is cohesive with altering out social and private life’ (Neurath 1944a, 46).

    Finally, we should address the reflexive value of the social sciences insofar as science plays the meta-theoretical and critical role of philosophy, displacing any alternative, autonomous and speculative source of insight. History of science, for instance, will require adequate classifications for the purposes of advancing correlations. In that regard, it will benefit from avoiding narrow dichotomies of classification and adopt, instead, the notion of theory – applied in economic planning – that aims at exploring all possibilities in the form of a matrix of combinations, realized and unrealized (in the tradition of encyclopedic and symbolic calculus of Llull and Leibniz). Neurath himself provided an application to the case of optics (Neurath 1916/1983 and Neurath 1944a, 42). Similarly for sociology, the search of an adequate classification of hypotheses in the first step.

    From a historical perspective, Neurath followed anthropologists such as Frazer and Levy-Bruhl considering magical thinking primordial and universal. It acted as a primitive, empirical and causal thinking with instrumental value and unlike metaphysics, according to Neurath it resembled the modern empiricist scientific world-conception and facilitated its introduction, –which replaced it with unified science.

    Notice, however, that the epistemological relativism associated with logical empiricism is not the outcome solely of such external sociological perspective or naturalistic and empirical considerations about scientific practice. It was implied by the philosophical rejection of Kant’s synthetic a priori and, as alternative to Kant’s approach to apriorism, the development of conventionalism by Carnap, Reichenbach and others inherited from Duhem, Poincaré and others concerning the exact sciences (Nemeth 2007, 283–4). Otherwise, Neurath pointed to the reflexivity of the social character of science itself and declared that sociologists argued, decided and acted in science as they themselves and others do in society. They are on the same boat with us; the boat of social sciences is just like that of the unified science and of social planning itself. This notion of social scientists, thinking up and putting in place possibilities under conditions of uncertainty, prompted Neurath’s final version of the boat analogy:

    Imagine sailors, who, far out at sea, transform the shape of their clumsy vessel from a more circular to a more fishlike one. They make use of some drifting timber, besides the timber of the old structure, to modify the skeleton and the hull of their vessel. But they cannot put the ship in dock in order to start from scratch. During their work they stay on the old structure and deal with heavy gales and thundering waves. In transforming their ship they take care that dangerous leakages do not occur. A new ship grows out of the old one, step by step—and while they are still building, the sailors may already be thinking of a new structure, and they will not always agree with one another. The whole business will go on in a way that we cannot even anticipate today. That is our fate. (Neurath 1944a, 47)
    Criticisms came from Viennese social scientists such as Karl Menger, Edgar Zilsel and Felix Kaufmann. Zilsel, an ally of the Circle, objected to the programmatic nature of Neurath’s foundational work, namely, that it was empiricism without empirical research. They all objected to the narrow strictures on the relation between the natural and the human sciences imposed by physicalism. Kaufmann, in particular, defended a phenomenological sociology, following Husserl much more closely than Carnap especially did, based on the value of introspective experience, although without the scientifically mysterious Weberian method of empathy (Uebel 2007, 255–57).

    Zilsel, Frank and Neurath had learned from Mach the value of history as a creative source of theoretical possibilities and critical perspective. Mach had called his approach ‘historical-critical method’ which echoed in his heirs’ ears with relevant references to Kant and Marx, and was understood to support the rejection of superhuman metaphysical inevitability. Like Reichenbach, Zilsel replaced the Kantian inquiry into the preconditions of the possibility scientific knowledge with more modest and anti-metaphysical projects, in his case, centered on the empirical—social political, economic-preconditions. Later on, Philip Frank advocated the empirical historical studies of science as part of the more complete answer to the question of the choice of hypotheses raised by Duhem and Poincaré, and the insufficiency of the logical inference that grounded their conventionalism. These are important sources and precedents of modern empirical studies of science."
    Cat, Jordi, "Otto Neurath", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2024 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2024/entries/neurath/>.




    _________________
    « La question n’est pas de constater que les gens vivent plus ou moins pauvrement, mais toujours d’une manière qui leur échappe. » -Guy Debord, Critique de la séparation (1961).

    « Rien de grand ne s’est jamais accompli dans le monde sans passion. » -Hegel, La Raison dans l'Histoire.

    « Mais parfois le plus clair regard aime aussi l’ombre. » -Friedrich Hölderlin, "Pain et Vin".

    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Admin


    Messages : 20709
    Date d'inscription : 12/08/2013
    Localisation : France

    Otto Neurath Empty Re: Otto Neurath

    Message par Johnathan R. Razorback Mer 20 Mar - 13:16

    "Educated in an environment rife with economic debate and spirit of social reform, Neurath intended his economic thinking to contribute to social happiness in practice and to economics in theory and method. To that effect he challenged a number of views influential at the turn of the century: e.g., Marx’s objective (labor) theory of value, Gustav Schmoller’s historicist inductivism, Max Weber’s ideal-type theory, Carl Menger’s Aristotelian, sometimes Platonist, essentialism and deductivism, as well as his and his followers’ commitment to subjective utility theory and the maximization of utility (e.g., Böhm-Bawerk and others focus on expected and marginal utility). Along the way, he also rejected his own father’s idealist spiritualism guiding social and economic reform.

    Neurath remained partly within the tradition of Menger’s so-called Austrian School of economics, embracing its decisionism in the technical form of a decision theory and a corresponding standard of rationality. Yet he also noted its limitations and conflict with his socialist epicurean goals. He rejected methodological individualism, the assumption of the value and even possibility of a precise absolute measures and calculus of utility especially involving an abstract and universal unit of calculation (and any uni-dimensionally commensurable alternatives). He defended, instead, an irreducibly multi-factorial notion of social welfare, use value and full utilization of resources over market standards of exchange value, monetary calculation and individual profit motive.

    Neurath shaped and changed his ideas while entering ongoing theorerical and methodological debates dating from the late nineteenth century: the socialism debate (centered around Marx), the method debate (centered around Schmoller and Menger), the value-judgment debate (centered around Weber and Sombart), the unity of science – or natural vs. human, or mental, sciences – debate (centered around Windelband and later Rickert and Dilthey), the socialization debate (centered around Kautsky, Adler, Bauer and Bernstein), and the socialist calculation debate (centered around von Mises, Weber and Hayek).

    Historiography or philosophy of history
    The debates over the historical sciences, a cornerstone of nineteen-century German intellectual culture, were prompted mainly by Leopold von Ranke’s rejection of Hegel’s idealist philosophy of history, with its universal and concept-driven laws of development. It was to be replaced with an empiricist emphasis on documentation of facts through original sources, and, unlike any nomological, generalist, approach characteristic of the natural sciences, an emphasis on the value of individual periods and cultures and human agency. Also cyclical models of history were proposed and rejected.

    The idealist tradition was based on the notion that knowledge, especially in the natural sciences, requires conceptual representation and Fichte’s student Emile Lask would speak of the hiatus irrationalis between reality itself and conceptual representation, and would note that, from the latter’s point of view, the former was infinitely complex (Oakes 1991). The general –the standard of understanding in the natural sciences– cannot fully capture the individual in its uniqueness –e.g. a historical hero and event. Moreover, the interpretive role of the historian towards texts, cultural artifacts, brought attention to their authors and human agency more generally.

    From the same viewpoint, German historiography soon developed a history sensitive to the plurality of relevant historical dimensions of historical phenomena and their causes Lamprecht, Meyer, Weber and others defended different approaches to cultural history, with attention to collective and institutional entities. Independently, from the idealist tradition and the philological and literary movements, German historiography developed an explicit interest in hermeneutics, emphasizing the role of understanding –after the historical projects of philological studies generally and scriptural interpretations of Biblical texts–; the program was associated with Schleiermacher, Böckh, Weber and Dilthey. Also influential on Neurath on this account were Goethe and Tönnies, who believed in the hold words and concepts had on experience, historical and ordinary.

    Goethe’s influence and Neurath’s romantic inheritance are manifest in two areas, morphology and historiography: holism, historical conditioning, role of pictures and metaphorical language in carrying physical theory and argument (ON 1973, 102–3), role of language, and thereby hypothetical elements, in establishing facts (Zemplen 2006). One may add that Neurath’s views fit with the romantic German tradition that emphasized will, life and holism,albeit against pseudorationalism, without metaphysics. Also, in 1908, Neurath appears listed as secretary of the Wiener Goethe Verein in its journal Chronik des Wiener Goethe-Vereins XXII, 39. Also Hans Hahn is listed as member.

    Neurath’s doctoral teachers, Meyer and Schmoller, represented the Young German historical school. Neurath’s early work on the history of economics placed him at the center of debates over historiography and the human sciences. He valued (1) empiricism without universal generalizations or laws of development, as well as (2) the synthesis between the subjective and objective, empirical and theoretical, aspects of interpreted materials without metaphysical commitments about the mind, and (3) the interest, found in Meyer and Schmoller, in the plurality of conditions and institutions that may characterize a historical phenomenon or period.

    The clear apprehension of different conditions and their relations effectively turn history into a catalogue of combinations out of which (conditional) lessons can be drawn. He would develop this idea in his notions of economic theory and history of science in the form of combinatorial generalizations of the number and kinds of arrangements of possibilities. These would form the conceptual or logical matrix in which to situate the subset of actual empirical historical cases realized (see below).

    A precedent Neurath was familiar with was the eighteenth-century Scottish mercantilist James Steuart, who also defended the examination of possible scenarios and “theories” before choosing to apply the most effective course of action to achieve fixed social goals. Other sources of scientific and reformist uses of history were his Wilhelm Neurath’s, although within a spiritualist, teleological normative framework, and Ernst Mach, with his critical, anti-absolutist historical-critical method.

    According to Sombart and Weber, the conceptual and interpretive dimension of history raised the issue of its value-ladenness in detriment of its scientific objectivity, particularly in the human sciences, such as political economy. Sombart pointed to the case of the notion of welfare. For Neurath, value judgments enter economic theory in terms of measured subjective pleasure of economic agents; or else in the evaluation of economic orders or plans relative to desiderata under consideration. But in neither case a measure of moral valuation is given by economic, or more generally, scientific theory. Objectivity in science was possibly insofar as it limited itself to description, even in causal terms, of relations to situations to be preferred on external grounds (Neurath 1911).

    As a matter of methodology in political economy, Neurath’s interests and education placed him in the middle of the debate over method that separated the German Historical School and the Austrian School, the historical and theoretical approach. The Historical School, whose most visible representative became Gustav Schmoller, defended a historical scope largely for the purpose of applying empirical statistical methods. It was associated with the Verein für Sozialpolitik for the purpose of discussing and providing objective empirical judgment to inform government policy and guide social reform. Schmoller argued that the inductive empirical methodology was more attuned to the complexity of social phenomena and the empirical and academic status of the research and researchers provided a level of neutrality that enhanced objectivity and neutrality in the face of ideological and political conflict (Cat 1996, Lindenfeld 1997, Grimmer-Solem 2003).

    The Austrian School, often seen represented by Carl Menger, father of the mathematician Karl Menger, favored a more purely theoretical approach, with conceptual analysis and deductive methods. Neurath defended a meta-methodological neutral stance that rejected the methodological debate as a pseudo-problem and assumed the compatibility and joint applicability of the two kinds of analyses: ‘Historical analyses often provided occasion for more general considerations, while theoretical research promotes the comprehension of organizational forms and induces historians to focus more closely on certain details.’ (Neurath 1911) History was central to both his synthetic theoretical approach and his future-oriented voluntaristic, constructive, reformist attitude.

    Subsequent methodological debates between Neurath and Carnap within the Vienna Circle and discussions of logical empiricism often seem to recapitulate some of the traits of the Methodenstreit – with Neurath adopting a synthesis of theory and history that is closer to Schmoller’s attitude under the contextualist rubric of history, in opposition to Carnap’s and Popper’s projects under the rubric of theory (Cat 1995, Cartwright et al. 1996).

    Neurath’s economics
    Neurath’s contributions to scientific epistemology have their roots in many of his views on economics. Neurath’s historical bend not only led him to the subject of his doctoral and postdoctoral research in economy of antiquity—Cicero and Egypt; it also shaped his pedagogical work and was reinforced by it, with an economics textbook co-edited with his first wife, Anne Shapire, in the form of an anthology of classical readings beginning with Plato and Aristotle. It is from the cultures of antiquity that Neurath gets much inspiration for his economic and social ideas: e.g., Egyptian economy in kind and visual languages (hieroglyphs) and Aristotelian economics of personal and social wealth (beyond money) and the economic value of war as source of income –also Epicurus on happiness more generally. Neurath paid attention to the different roles of money, in history and contemporary debates on monetary economies (Uebel 2004, Mooslechner 2008).

    Returning to Vienna after receiving his doctorate in Berlin in 1906, Neurath joined Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk’s postdoctoral seminar, also involving Friedrich von Wieser. There he encountered other young economists such as Ludwig von Mises, Otto Bauer and Joseph Schumpeter.

    The Austrian School, especially with Menger and Schumpeter, had developed a quantitative economic theory based on the notion of wealth reduced to exchange value and hence with a focus on market behavior. The ensuing theory was an a priori (hardly empirical psychology), heuristic, model developing the utilitarian calculus of subjective pleasure, the so-called homo economicus model of marginal utility theory: with utility calculations based on precise unitary measures—cardinal, not just ordinal measures of utility value and ordering of preferences—altogether a decision theory, in support of a price theory, in particular, a market equilibrium theory (Tribe 1995 ch. 6, Blaug 1996 and 1997). Rational decision-making, prediction and explanation relied ultimately on monetary calculations based on observable, uniform quantitative units such as prices and a focus on price signaling in market exchanges; losses provide indicators of inefficiency. The assumptions behind the theory relied on controversial and developing areas of empirical psychology, social and political theory and scientific epistemology. By contrast, Marx and energeticists advocated equally uniform and quantitative units of labor.

    Neurath challenged crucial assumptions, opposing both money and labor calculations (see Uebel 2004 and Turk 2018). In sum, the representation and comparative evaluation of organized economic totalities could not be reduced, according to Neurath, to uniform units of measurement of elementary constituents. Qualitative measurements of exact qualitative relations provide the only basis for in-kind, natural calculations of value and overall happiness and enable an administrative, unified, holistic model of socialized economy (patterned after wartime command economies maximizing efficiency in the availability and use of resources). The result was a rather inchoate combination of socialism and ecological economics in which the administrative economy is guided by egalitarian principles of distribution in the pursuit of maximum social happiness. From Aristotle and socialist literature Neurath adopted the household economic notion of wealth based on use value and welfare. Economists, he stressed from a consequentialist perspective, are interested in finding out what the conditions of the wealth of people are and which institutions increase it and which decrease it (Neurath 1917/2004, 328). The challenge remained to defend the rationality and objectivity, the fairness of decision-making in the alternative framework. As a personal matter as well as a matter of social justice, economic and political theory required a representation of wealth and its optimal allocation.

    Tackling ‘the problem of pleasure maximum’, in the early 1910s, Neurath argued that cardinal measures for comparative utility, or pleasure values, could not be determined for the same individual, much less for different individuals (Neurath 1912/1973). The rejection of cardinality as a framework for representing utility, and wealth, resorted to considerations similar to ones introduced in empirical psychology by Fechner quantitative psycho-physics and more recently Duhem’s conceptual discussion of physical measurement and quantification via the use of scales (Fechner 1860 and Duhem 1906), among them the importance in order to construct cardinal units – and not just ordering relations – of fixing at least a zero point, and establish one end of a scale. Neurath also rejected, independently, the in-principle additivity of utility functions, that is, of pleasures. Despite the exact relations modeled after inequalities and additive operations in algebraic logic, social utility maxima cannot be calculated univocally. Interpersonal comparisons (even for the same individual over time) of utility are not generally available; and when they are, then it is the unitary measures which are not. In conclusion, cardinal unitary measures are not necessary for comparability; and comparability is neither necessary nor sufficient for choice, or, specifically, economic, social or political decision-making, to achieve a desired state of welfare.

    Without a unitary measure, and an algorithmic calculation method for decision-making, Neurath was articulating and urging a more general type of framework: a shift from a model of market economy to models of administrative economy [Verwaltungswirtschaft] or economy in kind [Naturalwirtschaft]. Market economy, in any of its varieties, assumes a framework in which ‘people influence each other’s actions exclusively by means of the higher and lower qualities of life that result from the process of exchange’ with the main conditioning factors of profit and loss, and the goals of maximizing the first kind and minimizing the second. An administrative economy can ‘by rewards and penalties, prompt the individuals to do things which they would not have done in an economy characterized by exchange, because without these rewards and penalties the consequences would have been different.’ (Neurath 1917/2004, 321).

    The historical geopolitical circumstances of Central Europe in the 1910s and a commission from the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace enabled Neurath to study war economies as empirical realizations of administrative models (Neurath 1919/1973, 123–157). In 1913 he would propose a new discipline, war economics. The goal was to learn from wartime political crises in order to solve peacetime economic crises. The latter he associated with failures of market capitalism, which included not just business cycles but artificial scarcity through waste and underproduction. Neurath drew attention to examples of war economies in antiquity—for instance in Egypt—noting their evolution from monetary exchange and a profit motive to organized barter and a productivity motive. He also became acquainted with economic studies of past wars, including the Napoleonic Wars and the American Civil War, that formed a minor tradition within political economy challenged by rising attention to the economic role of private individual agents. In addition to his familiarity with Aristotle, Neurath was familiar with studies by seventeenth-, eighteenth-, and nineteenth-century authors such as Caspar Klock, Adam Ferguson, Patrick Colquhoun, Joseph Lowe, Henry George, Ludwig Gustav von Gülich, Jakob Reiser and Adolf Jöhr.

    The Carnegie Endowment for International Peace Year Book for 1912, lists several Neurath projects to be completed in 1913 and 1914: ‘Austrian and Servian [sic] loans, 1908–09’, ‘Rivalry among states with respect to capitalist investments in foreign countries—Adriatic railway’, ‘circulation of and revenue from private economic property’, ‘Effect of war upon the supply of the world with food and raw material’, ‘Stimulation or depression of nations by war (war and living conditions)’. ‘Influence of annexation upon the economic life of the annexing state and upon the state whose territory has been annexed’, ‘annexation of half-civilized or uncivilized peoples, etc.’, ‘Economic effects of withdrawing men from industrial pursuits to enter the army and navy’, ‘Compulsorily-Austrian labor market, 1866–78–1904’, ‘Non-compulsorily-Austrian labor market, 1866–78–1904’, ‘Loans for armaments—forms of loans’, ‘Effects of war on economic conditions’ (C.E.I.P. Year Book for 1912, 93). Three works by Neurath associated with political economist Eugene von Philippovich of the University of Vienna as economics and history editor listed as indefinitely delayed by the war: ‘The effects of the Balkan wars on Austria-Hungary, with special regard to Serbia, Bulgaria, Roumania, Russia, Montenegro, Albania, Italy, Switzerland and Germany’; ‘War and order of life. The liquidity, productivity and rentability of the wealth of nations in the case of war’; and (with Professor Harald Westergaard, professor of political science and statistics at the University of Copenhagen as editor) ‘Preliminary statistical studies in Old Servia [sic]’ (C.E.I.P.Year Book for 1915, 90).

    Neurath had further opportunity to research and help administer war economies during World War I. He was appointed to the Ministry of War, where he headed a new General War and Economics Section of the Scientific Committee for War Economy. Ironically, he briefly counted with the (reluctant) help of Ludwig von Mises.

    A war economy planned production and distribution to meet perceived (and calculated) needs during wartime. An economy in kind similarly planned for peacetime. Neurath found in war economies the displayed advantages of speed of decision and execution, optimal distribution of means relative to military goals, and increased evaluation and utilization of invention. Two disadvantages resulting from centralized decision-making might be the ineffective replacement of simple exchanges and the reduction of productivity, which could be reduced, as Lenin learned, through the methods of Taylorism (Tribe 1995, 155). Social and economic theory, and scientific methodology, had become for Neurath matters of theory and of actual practice, of the relation between theory and practice, and, just as important, of a theory of practice (Neurath 1913/1983).

    In opposition to the reductive notion of monetary wealth, Neurath’s complex, multi-factorial notion of wealth as happiness distinguished between the notion of quality of life – with its degrees of intensity – and the basis of life. The former is the complex of experiences collected under the rubrics pleasure, happiness and welfare. The latter is ground for the complexes of objective conditions that cause the corresponding subjective experiences and he called conditions of life.

    Subjective and objective conditions would be tracked by means of a universal statistics of incommensurable goods, and there were to be portrayed holistically by a life physiognomy: ‘what food the individuals consume per year, what their housing conditions are, what and how much they read, what their experiences are in family life, how much they work, how often and how seriously they fall ill, how much time they spend walking, attending religious services, enjoying art, etc.’ (Neurath 1917/2004, 326). Calculation in kind [Naturalrechnung] would involve a realistic consideration of incommensurable qualitative possibilities, a plurality of individuals, incomplete insight in the face of complexity, and, no less important, the necessity to act. The different possible silhouettes would suggest possible economic plans to choose from.

    As a result, calculation in kind required a new form of practical reasoning, one far from the astronomical, Laplacean ideal in science and the Cartesian rationalist and individualistic ideal in philosophy, — which he referred to as “pseudorationality” and he subsequently recognized in Popper’s views. The alternative mode of calculation was based on (a) judgment (‘directly judge the desirability’ of possibilities, Neurath 1919/1973, 146), (b) justification (by showing ‘that it fits into the whole pattern of personal life of which we approve’, Neurath 1928/1973, 249), and (c) extra-logical factors or auxiliary motives. Tossing a coin is just one example of such motives as causes of decisions and thereby of actions (Neurath 1913/1983, 1917/2004); Neurath commended it over choices made ‘with the help of an inadequate metaphysical theory’ (Neurath 1912/1973, 122). A similar role was played by epistemic and social aims such as unity and coordination and economic constraints such as the avoidance of crises of overproduction and artificial scarcity (since Marx’s Capital referred to as the production anarchism, wastefulness, madness or chaos of the market) (Neurath 1917/2004, 322). Neurath’s voluntarism and his arguments anticipated much contemporary discussions of practical rationality under conditions of incomparability and incommensurability (see, for instance, Chang 1997, and O’Neill 2002).

    Whereas an economy in kind requires calculation in kind, calculation in kind did not imply economy in kind. Neurath’s initial arguments after World War I were intended to defend economy in kind as a moneyless, marketless economy, where monetary calculations are insufficient and calculations in kind are universal and necessary. This implies the weaker claim against market fundamentalism, namely, that the universality of monetary, or profit-based calculations are the basis for rational decisions about labor and goods. In exile, after the Nazi annexation of Austria, Neurath’s arguments shifted towards the weaker claim (Uebel 2008).

    The total dimension of the social and economic plan assumed plurality of people’s interests and their representation. Despite the centralized structure of his planning models, Neurath consistently defended, at least intended, his models to be democratic: first in the sense of representation, which from a technical—scientific and empirical- viewpoint was expressed through statistical surveys and informed citizen participation (hence the relevance of empirical visual languages as vehicles of public education at the service of democracy); second, in the sense of compromise (‘cooperative compromise’), namely, non-additive, negotiated cooperation with the aim of achieving an otherwise impossible state of welfare or order of life; third, freedom to have a multiplicity of loyalties and tolerance towards differences and multiplicity of attitudes -even within one’s own behavior, as ‘a human being full of contradiction’, including conflict with experts and echoing his own rejection in 1913 of a Cartesian logical unity as model for the psychological unity of the self (Neurath 1942/1973, 429)- (on pluralism, see O’Neill 1998 and 2008; also Sandner 2014).

    Socialization debates: Political and theoretical developments
    Besides the socialist tradition and debates, Austria had its own tradition of scientific utopianism based on Mach’s empiricist interest in energy as fundamental notion and his technological optimism. Leading figures were Josef Popper-Lynkeus and Carl Ballod (known also under the pen-name Ballod-Atlanticus), who proposed plans for the rational, fair and sustainable allocation of exhaustible energy and materials, established through statistical empirical methods to address the capitalist problems (crises) of production and distribution at the root of much poverty, and realized through the notions of a national peacetime work draft, a nutrition army, and the nationalization of distribution (Popper-Lynkeus 1912, Ballod 1898).

    The calculations involved statistical surveys and assessments of nutrition and living conditions needs and work hours needed for producing them. Energy and time units were fundamental; time units were the standard cardinal unity of measurement in socialist calculations. One of the classical problems was the so-called imputation problem, of calculating the proportional contribution of production goods in joint production. Marx solved the problem and the parallel problem for consumer goods with the non-subjective labor theory of value, in terms of units of measurement for the amount of labor required for their production. The utopianist contributions went beyond the Marxist model of evolution of capitalism into modeling proposals now categorized as ecological economics (Martinez-Alier 1987, O’Neill 1993 and 2002).

    From a technical point of view, scientific utopianism is an approach to social engineering in terms of the exploration of possible constructions for alternative social scenarios. Like mechanical engineering, according to Neurath, these utopian social constructions could be characterized as follows:

    (1) They stem from imaginary and conceptual fictions and possibilities (‘the great task of consciously cultivating the future and the possible’); (2) they involve notions of balance and conservation in ‘comprehensive administration of energy and power’, (3) a collective dimension in the role and value of collaboration, (4) contextual and holistic social and historical aspects of thought, language and conventions (‘it is not a single individual who can really think new notions through to the end, but only whole groups or generations. Thinking, too, is a collective occurrence. Thus the Marxist must from the outset keep with a special vigour to historical experience’ Neurath 1928/1973, 293), (5) a pragmatic dimension in decision-making that connects planning with action and transformation of reality (‘successful collaboration id possible only when those who act fix on one possibility, whether by agreement or by propaganda. This choice itself is a matter of action and resolution, but that does not mean’, insisted Neurath, ‘that such action has no scientific basis’ Neurath 1928/1973, 293) and (6) a holistic dimension, insofar as socialization and planning are forms of ‘total organizations’, which must engage the economy as a whole (and from above), (7) in a unified format so that for any such model one may say that a ‘unified program would have coordinated and unified action’ (Neurath 1919/1973, 150–155, and Neurath 1920/1973, 19).

    History would provide yet again the opportunity for insight and practice. The end of World War I brought with it the collapse of the German economy, the end of the rule of the Kaiser and his latest conservative government. Caught in the tide of communist revolutionary changes that was sweeping Eastern Europe, two short-lived Soviet republics were declared. In November 1918, the office of the Chancellor was occupied by Friedrich Ebert, a Majority Social Democrat, and under pressure from the now powerful Workers and Soldiers Council movement the new government established a commission to plan a comprehensive socialization of the economy. At the same time, Bavaria and Saxony declared a soviet republic, albeit in Bavaria presided by the Independent Socialist Kurt Eisner. Neurath, crafted a socialization plan for Saxony (the Kranold-Neurath-Schumann plan), and in January 1919 presented his ideas to the new Bavarian government and the Munich workers (Neurath 1973, ch 1, 1–83, Neurath 1920/2004, 345–370, Cat et al 1995, Uebel 2004). He was dismissed by the chairman of the socialization commission and Munich professor of economics, Lujo Brentano, as an ‘ancient-Egyptian romantic economist’ (which in a more interesting sense he was). But his ideas received the support of the industrialist, chairman of AEG, Walther Rathenau. While the assassination of Eisner led to the violent suppression of the Bavarian soviet republic, in March Neurath was appointed president of the central planning office for Bavaria. Carl Ballod was put in charge of calculation in kind. Neurath requested that his position be considered of a nonpolitical administrator as he considered his task as a technical one, with scientific status and ideologically neutrality. After a third, now communist, government’s fall and arrest, the same considerations at his trial (and a statement by Weber) kept him out of prison in 1921, although also out of Germany. He was eventually forced to return to Austria, where he joined the more socially oriented socialization efforts (with a focus on housing, education, etc) led by the Austro-Marxist Otto Bauer, among others, in what had become Red Vienna (Cartwright et al. 1996).

    Neurath’s technical model of natural, that is, non-monetary, economics became after World War I a matter of socialist politics and part of the literature on socialization. As a social scientist, his main strategy for linking his work with the Marxist tradition was to defend it alongside Marx’s own work as scientific in character, as examples of social science. A meta-theoretical—epistemological, methodological- perspective resulted from his own familiarity with a number of debates over disciplinary issues in the human sciences, and philosophical issues and positions regarding the natural sciences rooted in Mach’s empiricism and Poincaré and Duhem’s conventionalism, with their own critical, anti-metaphysical, naturalistic and pragmatist connotations.

    Neurath’s position sat uncomfortably among a number of economic and political models attempting to develop Marxism, or socialism, as an alternative to monetary market capitalism: Eduard Bernstein’s ethical revisionism and Karl Kautsky’s Social Democratic Marxist orthodoxy and agrarianism, Victor Adler, Max Adler and Otto Bauer and others’ personalist, cultural and non-territorial Austro-Marxism, Karl Korsch’s workers council democracy, Bolshevism’s dictatorship of the proletariat or Rosa Luxemburg’s Spartacism, without parliamentary representation. Unlike market socialists such as Helen Bauer, Neurath rejected the role of money. Unlike orthodox Marxism, Neurath’s central planning rejected the reliance of units of measurement of work and the objective content of price measurements, and economic determinism. His humanist, welfarist, voluntarist, scientific utopianism was an engineered epicurean socialism (closer in spirit to young-Marx’s philosophy) (Neurath 1928/1973, 284–90, Uebel 2004, Sandner 2008). Like the Austro-Marxists, especially the neo-Kantian Max Adler, Neurath rejected a radical materialist, mechanistic and economic reductionism, valuing a plurality of institutions and cultural and educational pursuits. The spirit of pluralism, revisionism and heterodoxy Austro-Marxism introduced in Austrian political culture enabled Neurath’s hybrid, deflationary, critical views. Unlike Bauer and Kautsky, however, or Schmoller’s German Young Historical School and corresponding members of Verein fur Sozialpolitik, he rejected gradual change and partial socialization. Like his father, Wilhelm Neurath, he advocated pan-cartelism, bringing together all industries under government control, without immediate full nationalization (expropriation) or replacement of expert owners and managers with managing workers councils (Cartwright et al 1996, Uebel 1995, Nemeth et al. 2008).

    Besides criticisms from the socialist camp, Neurath faced criticism from early defenders of free-market economics: Max Weber, Ludwig von Mises, and Friedrich von Hayek (Lavoie 1985, Chaloupek 1990, Vaughn 1994, O’Neill 1998 and 2008, Steele 1999; Uebel 2004 and 2019; Turk 2018; only O’Neill acknowledges and does some justice to Neurath’s contribution). Neurath was thus drawn into meta-theoretical debates over the rationality, objectivity and informativeness of an economy.

    For Weber, discussions of rationality and objectivity were central to his inquiries into the sociology of power and bureaucracy and the nature of scientific disciplines. Weber distinguished between substantive (ends) and formal (means-end, practical) rationality,A planned economy requires a rational plan, and a rational plan requires in turn a method warranting the possibility of determining an outcome in the process of making a decision to take a course of action. Outside the household, with its accounting largely based on the use value of goods, the market of goods with exchange value offers the possibility of using their monetary price as a universal unit of value and calculation of profitability (Weber 1921). This in turn determines the solutions to higher-order calculation problems and, by inclusion, the outcomes of decision-making processes. Moreover, the monetary calculation of profitability is as objective as it is formal and precise.

    Mises pointed to commensurability as the root of objectivity of rational calculation of decision of production and allocation of consumption and production goods (Mises 1920/1935 and 1922). Socialism in the form of Neurath’s model of moneyless economy is, then, ex hypothese, the abolition of rational economy (Mises 1920/1935, 110). Mises added a practical objection, in terms of one individual, Robinson Crusoe’s capabilities: ‘No single man can ever master all the possibilities of production, innumerable as they are, as to be in a position to make straightway evident judgments of value without the aid of some system of computation.’ (in Hayek 1935, 102).

    Hayek confronted Neurath on the problem of coordination of action in a pluralistic society with dispersed knowledge. Hayek’s criticisms shared the Austrian cognitive (and practical) perspective, in his case to consider the market an efficient and reliable information-communication mechanism but the solution to the coordination problem is non-discursive to the extent that all information is communicated by relative prices. These are the mechanism and information on which rational decision-making and spontaneous coordination and cooperation (catallaxy) would be based (Hayek 1935, O’Neill 1998).

    Among Austrians, the debate was fought along a line that distinguished two options only, either monetary market economy or moneyless central planning. But Neurath entered the debate with an altogether different notion of rationality, and of objectivity as well. Recall his distinction between rationality and pseudorationality. The latter ‘treats everything as calculable’ (Neurath 1942/1973, 402) and analyzable and representable by precise formulas. For Neurath, the ‘logical correctness’ of the method is not correlated with its ‘logical precision’ (Neurath 1935/1987, 71–72). Neurath’s solution to coordination and cooperation with pluralism is discursive and humanist. The rationality of central planning is based on the deliberative balancing of possible sets of specific conditions and units that characterize different possible life situations. It is also based on the fact that the choice is somewhat determined by a given specific goal. Here Neurath offered a corresponding boat analogy, this time a battleship from the context of war economy, the original source of empirical data and motivation for his model of moneyless economy (hehd introduced a similar analogy first in 1913):

    ‘Besides modern commercial activities, military activities have also been rationalized to a very high degree. ‘Success in battle’ is similar to ‘gains in a venture’. Now let us see, e.g., how the captain of a battleship proceeds when he is forced to fight far from home. As commanding officer, he takes into account the course of the ship, the power of the engines, the range of the guns, the stores of ammunition, the torpedoes, and the food supplies, but certainly not the prices of the individual elements. He bases his calculations on numerous specific units which he may even represent to himself in graphic terms, as we can also imagine a graphic representation of the economic plan of a natural macroeconomy. This apparatus, which is rationalized through and through, is composed of people and things, just like an economy, the only difference being that the war apparatus is considered from the point of view of winning a battle and an economy from the point of view of changing life situations…The captain of the battleship does not have a formula which would allow him to think of substituting a number of torpedoes for a canon, or a number of men for an armoured plate. While people readily admit that the military leadership can operate without a general unit, they do not want to make the same assumption for the economic leadership.’ (Neurath 1935/1987, 108)

    In 1928 he made a similar methodological point explicitly within the context of economics:

    The most careful and conscientious, perhaps statistical, consideration of all circumstances does not give us a unit for calculation. How can one numerically compare, beyond the amounts, things like the protection of man-power with the protection of coal deposits? In spite of the most careful assessment of all quantities, with due regard to numerical estimated coal deposits yet unexploited, one can still not mark each plan by a number obtained through additions and subtractions, etc., and then take the plan which gives the biggest number. Economic plans can be compared only in the way one compares the pears and books; one can prefer one plan to another only on the basis of a total estimate. (Neurath 1928/1973, 263–4)

    This total estimate, which constitutes the grounds for rationality, commensurability and decision-making, is based on desired configurations of social and economic goals. Examples of specific economic goals for Neurath are the effective allocation of exhaustible resources, the elimination of under-restricted production and destruction of goods and the misuse of man-power that monetary calculation allows. These goals may be more specific and are always contingent. Empirical data make them available to the people’s representatives and decisions are then reached by common sense after experts have conceived of and proposed a number of informed possible theoretical alternatives:

    Comparison between wholes (plans) could not always rest on commensurability of their parts:

    The question might arise, should one protect coal mines or put greater strain on men? The answer depends for example on whether one thinks that hydraulic power may be sufficiently developed or that solar heat might come to be better used, etc. If one believes the latter, one may ‘spend’ coal more freely and will hardly waste human effort where coal can be used. If however one is afraid that when one generation uses too much coal thousands will freeze to death in the future, one might use more human power and save coal. Such and many other non-technical matters determine the choice of a technically calculable plan … we can see no possibility of reducing the production plan to some kind of unit and then to compare the various plans in terms of such units…. (Neurath 1928/1973, 263)

    The rationality of economic planning is, as it is for science generally, not an arbitrary but a pragmatic matter. It does not lack a model of justification, but Neurath’s model differs from the one adopted by Mises (O’Neill 1998). It is in this sense that Hayek’s subsequent contribution with an emphasis on information as the basis for an argument against central planning redefined the calculation debates. For Neurath, to justify a belief or a decision meant ‘to show that it fits into the whole pattern of personal life of which we approve.’(Neurath 1928/1973, 249) Rationality is thus based on historically and socially contingent values. It is also fallible and equivocal. So, in early as well as in later essays, Neurath dismissed also in the economic context the appeal to pseudorational precise calculations preferred on the mere grounds that they might offer fixed outcomes to be considered the best.

    Regarding objectivity, Neurath made clear in ‘What is Meant by a Rational Economic Theory?’ that economic thinking in central planning is committed to a ‘consistently scientific language’ and to ‘objective connections’ (Neurath 1935/1987). This objectivity is provided by the language of physicalism, of material things and structures in space and time, not of physical theory. And it underwrites the generality of the scope of economy in kind, from market goods and maximum profit to the welfare of the population. As he put it, ‘it is precisely the strict physicalists, those who seek to carry out the program of unified science, who have no objections to the concept ‘welfare’.’(ibid., 73) Objectivity and unification go together once again. The unified language of physicalism guarantees the public and social character of knowledge in the form of universal statistics, often neglected or kept secret in capitalist systems. But all this information, in the absence of the market, is the basis of unified central planning. Hence, he stated in 1919, ‘a socialist economy knows no economic statistical secrets.’(Neurath 1919/1974, 141)

    Finally, the objectivity of physicalism in the service of central planning without money replaces the quantitative market prices as universal equivalent or general unit with unified yet specific units of kinds of things. Both general and specific units contribute to their objective and scientific nature through the use of numbers. Neurath emphasized that with a universal statistics of specific units ‘ ‘natural calculation’ is applicable in all cases where there is talk of ‘quantities of welfare’.’ (ibid., 72) But this leads to a less reductionistic kind of conceptual unification. Whereas the monetary general unit eliminates important differences among many kinds of goods making them directly commensurable, the use of specific unit allows for a general rational economics respecting heterogeneity among kinds of things such as health and disease, which for Neurath are ‘not objects to be bought and sold.’

    This anti-reductionistic attitude enabled Neurath to address Mises’s argument from complexity. But Neurath’s notion of social reality as a complex comprised of entities of different kinds suggests a holistic approach to its description and prediction. Planning and socialization can only take place for the whole and from above. This holistic perspective demands unified knowledge of the whole.

    Already in 1919 Neurath pointed out explicitly that successful planning required a unified program. Subsequently, in the broader context of scientific methodology Neurath argued that given the complexity of social phenomena—often involving natural events- successful prediction requires the unity of the sciences at the point of action (Cat et al. 1996 and in Cartwright et al. 1996). Yet, for him understanding of social groups rendered physical knowledge of the behavior of the microscopic material constituents irrelevant. By the time of Neurath’s exile from Nazi Austria, he had come to advocate the weaker notion of calculation in kind over the centrally planned economies in kind. Yet the holistic scientific attitude to planning was not out of his view of governance, whether of society or science. Neurath would still speak in the early 1940s of the ‘orchestration of the sciences, and, correspondingly, in his review of Hayek’s The Road to Serfdom in 1945 he would speak of planning as ‘orchestration of ways of living’ (Neurath 1945, 121). He would also write in 1943 in his essay ‘Planning or Managerial Revolution?’ that ‘sometimes it is less difficult to manage a bigger enterprise as a whole than the smaller units which are its parts.’ (Neurath 1943, 153)

    Rationality, objectivity and unity, were for Neurath radically social. Science is linked to society in at least three ways. Neurath, the sociologist, showed through word and work that society falls within scope of application of science. Neurath, the socialist, wanted science, and scientific philosophy, to serve society by promoting freedom and welfare. Neurath, the philosopher of science, argued that science has social structure and values that must be shared by the society to which it belongs. The republic of scientists is not Plato’s republic."
    -Cat, Jordi, "Otto Neurath", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2024 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2024/entries/neurath/>.




    _________________
    « La question n’est pas de constater que les gens vivent plus ou moins pauvrement, mais toujours d’une manière qui leur échappe. » -Guy Debord, Critique de la séparation (1961).

    « Rien de grand ne s’est jamais accompli dans le monde sans passion. » -Hegel, La Raison dans l'Histoire.

    « Mais parfois le plus clair regard aime aussi l’ombre. » -Friedrich Hölderlin, "Pain et Vin".


    Contenu sponsorisé


    Otto Neurath Empty Re: Otto Neurath

    Message par Contenu sponsorisé


      La date/heure actuelle est Ven 8 Nov - 19:40