L'Académie nouvelle

Vous souhaitez réagir à ce message ? Créez un compte en quelques clics ou connectez-vous pour continuer.
L'Académie nouvelle

Forum d'archivage politique et scientifique

Le Deal du moment : -38%
Ecran PC gaming 23,8″ – ACER KG241Y P3bip ...
Voir le deal
99.99 €

    Frank Straus Meyer, In Defende of Freedom and Related Essays

    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Admin


    Messages : 20741
    Date d'inscription : 12/08/2013
    Localisation : France

    Frank Straus Meyer, In Defende of Freedom and Related Essays Empty Frank Straus Meyer, In Defende of Freedom and Related Essays

    Message par Johnathan R. Razorback Dim 3 Fév - 12:52

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Frank_Meyer_(political_philosopher)

    "Frank Straus Meyer was a leader in the founding generation of post-World War II American conservatism. Like Whittaker Chambers, Max Eastman, and John Dos Passos, he embraced conservatism after having been a member of the Communist Party, and like them, too, Meyer became a fierce and unrelenting foe of communism and the Soviet Union that sponsored its spread worldwide." (p.XI)

    "While at Oxford he was a well-known radical student leader and secret member of the Communist Party, taking instruction from his party handlers on his duties as a student activist. This radical phase continued through his studies at the London School of Economics (1932-34) and at the University of Chicago (1934-38). In 1940 Meyer married Elsie Bown, who became his lifelong intellectual and political companion. They made their home on Ohayo Mountain Road in Woodstock, New York. Here, over the years, the Meyers welcomed countless visitors for memorable nights of conversation, food and drink, and song. Their two sons are John C. and Eugene B. Meyer. Always the intellectual, Meyer, who turned to communism through a study of Marxist texts, began an agonizing reappraisal of his beliefs after reading F. A. Hayek's The Road to Serfdom while serving in the U.S. Army during World War II. In 1945, after fourteen years of active service at its direction, Meyer made a complete break with the party." (p.XII-XIII)

    "Meyer's intellectual road from Marxist collectivism to the defense of individual liberty was paralleled by another, more drawn out, and evidently more wrenching spiritual journey that probably began during his days at Oxford. On the day of his death this proud Jew was baptized into the Catholic Church." (p.XV)

    "For many readers Meyer's fusionism (as it was called by his friendly adversary L. Brent Bozell) will remain convincing." (p.XXI)
    -William C. Dennis, préface à Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.

    "When two or three years ago Russell Kirk, then a member of the faculty of Michigan State College, published a volume called The Conservative Mind, he hardly expected, it is to be presumed, that within a short time it would make him the major prophet of a flourishing new movement. But the emergence of the New Conservatism, which has for some time filled the columns of the quarterlies and magazines of opinion and is now spilling out into the larger world, can indeed be accurately correlated with the appearance of that book." (p.3)

    "This fundamental compatibility with the collectivist trend of the time which comes out so blatantly in Mr. Rossiter has been implicit in the New Conservatism from the beginning, despite much just and tonic criticism of positivist ethics and the blatant centralizing tone of the "liberal" atmosphere by Russell Kirk and his more serious colleagues."

    "The term "liberal" has for some time now been captured by the proponents of a powerful state and a controlled economy and has been corrupted into the opposite of its true meaning. To be conservative has, therefore, by usage and consent come to mean to be an opponent of that false "liberalism." From a certain point of view there has been logic to this custom, when by conservative was understood loyalty to the established traditions of the Constitution and to a free American social structure, as over against the Roosevelt revolution." (p.4)

    "The fundamental political issue today is that between, on the one hand, collectivism and statism which merge gradually into totalitarianism and, on the other, what used to be called liberalism, what we may perhaps call individualism: the principles of the primacy of the individual, the division of power, the limitation of government, the freedom of the economy. This is not a problem of tone or attitude, not a difference between the conservative and the radical temperament; it is a difference of principle. What is at stake are fundamental concepts of the relationship of individual men to a society and the institutions of a society." (p.5)

    "The mantle of the conservative tone can well befit the established order of the welfare society. Mter all, that order is in its twenty-third year since the fateful election of 1932. The New Conservatism is, on an intellectual level, a natural complement to the Eisenhower version of Rooseveltism." (p.6)

    "The entire sphere of economic activity must remain free of political control. For only the strict separation of the sources of a man's material existence-property, employment, provision for illness and old age-from political institutions can enable him to maintain his independence of them. And further, if the state, which is the legal repository of force for the preservation of the conditions of peaceful civil life and for defense against external enemies, gains control over any other sphere of human activity, the very possibility of effective division of power is gone." (p.8 )

    "However much one may respect Burke's stand as a practical statesman, it is impossible to derive a firm political position from him. As Richard Weaver has said: "Of clear rational principle he had a mortal distrust ... it would be blindness to take him as a mentor." (p.10)

    "Their judgment is good. Only the principles of individual freedom-to Dr. Kirk the "conservatism of desolation" -can call a halt to the march of collectivism." (p.13)
    -Frank Straus Meyer, "Collectivism Rebaptized", july 1955, in Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.

    "For the first time in modern America a whole school of thought has consciously challenged the very foundations of collectivist Liberalism ; two intellectually serious journals, Modern Age and National Review, have established themselves integrally in the life of the nation ; and an increasing number of the newer generation of undergraduates, graduate students, and young instructors in the universities openly range themselves against the prevailing Liberal orthodoxy."

    "I ask the indulgence of my readers in accepting the word "conservative" as an overall term to include the two streams of thought that in practice unite to oppose the reigning ideology of collectivist Liberalism. I believe that those two streams of thought, although they are sometimes presented as mutually
    incompatible, can in reality be united within a single broad conservative political theory
    ." (p.15)

    "Their opposition, which takes many forms, is essentially a division between those who abstract from the corpus of Western belief its stress upon freedom and upon the innate importance of the individual person (what we may call the "libertarian" position) and those who, drawing upon the same source, stress value and virtue and order (what we may call the "traditionalist" position).

    But the source from which both draw, the continuing consciousness of Western civilization, has been specifically distinguished by its ability to hold these apparently opposed ends in balance and tension, and in fact the two positions which confront each other today in American conservative discourse both implicitly accept, to a large degree, the ends of the other.

    Without the implicit acceptance of an absolute ground of value, the preeminence of the person as criterion of political and social thought and action has no philosophical foundation, and freedom would be only a meaningless excitation and could never become the serious goal of a serious politics. On the other hand, the belief in virtue as the end of men's being implicitly recognizes the necessity of freedom to choose that end ; otherwise, virtue could be no more than a conditioned tropism. And the raising of order to the rank of an end overshadowing and subordinating the individual person would make of order not what the traditionalist conservative means by it, but the rule of totalitarian authority, inhuman and subhuman.

    On neither side is there a purposeful, philosophically founded rejection of the ends the other side proclaims. Rather, each side emphasizes so strongly the aspect of the great tradition of the West which it sees as decisive that distortion sets in. The place of its goals in the total tradition of the West is lost sight of, and the complementary interdependence of freedom and virtue, of the individual person and political order, is forgotten
    ." (p.16)

    "Both extremes are selfdefeating: truth withers when freedom dies, however righteous the authority that kills it; and free individualism uninformed by moral value rots at its core and soon brings about conditions that pave the way for surrender to tyranny." (p.17)

    "What the conservative is committed to conserve is not simply whatever happen to be the established conditions of a few years or a few decades, but the consensus of his civilization, of his country, as that consensus over the centuries has reflected truth derived from the very constitution of being. We are today historically in a situation created by thirty years of slow and insidious revolution at home and a half century of violent open revolution abroad. To conserve the true and the good under these circumstances is to restore an understanding (and a social structure reflecting that understanding) which has been all but buried ; it is not to preserve the transient customs and prescriptions of the present.

    It is here that the dilemma of conservatism affects our present doctrinal discussion. The need in our circumstances for the most vigorous use of reason to combat the collectivist, scientistic, amoral wave of the present tends to induce in the libertarian an apotheosis of reason and the neglect of tradition and prescription (which he identifies with the prevailing prescriptions of the present). The traditionalist, suspecting in this libertarian tendency the same fever to impose upon men an abstract speculative ideology that has characterized the revolution of our time-as well as the French Revolution and its spiritual forebears-tends to recoil and in his turn to press a one-sided position. Too often he confounds reason and principle with "demon ideology." Rather than justly insisting upon the limits of reason-the finite bounds of the purview of any one man or anyone generation and the responsibility to employ reason in the context of continuing tradition-he seems sometimes to turn his back on reason altogether and to place the claims of custom and prescription in irreconcilable opposition to it
    ." (p.18)

    "When a revolutionary force shatters the unity and balance of civilization -then conservatism must be of another sort if it is to fulfill its responsibility. It is not and cannot be limited to that uncritical acceptance, that uncomplicated reverence, which is the essence of natural conservatism." (p.19)

    "What is required of us is a conscious conservatism, a clearly principled restatement in new circumstances of philosophical and political truth. This conscious conservatism cannot be a simple piety, although in a deep sense it must have piety towards the constitution of being. Nevertheless in its consciousness it necessarily reflects a reaction to the rude break the revolution has made in the continuity of human wisdom. It is called forth by a sense of the loss which that cutting off has created. It cannot now be identical with the natural conservatism towards which it yearns. The world in which it exists is the revolutionary world. [...] Today's conservatism cannot simply affirm. It must select and adjudge." (p.20)

    "Like Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, confronting the chaos in the body politic and in the minds of men created by the overweening pride of the Athenian demos, we do not live in the happy age of a natural conservatism. We cannot simply revere ; we cannot uncritically follow tradition."(p.21)

    "We need to reject the utilitarian ethics and the secular progressivism that classical liberalism has also passed on to us.

    Nineteenth-century conservatism, with all its understanding of the preeminence of virtue and value, for all its piety towards the continuing tradition of mankind, was far too cavalier to the claims of freedom, far too ready to subordinate the individual person to the authority of state or society.
    " (p.22)

    "Although the classical liberal forgot -and the contemporary libertarian conservative sometimes tends to forget-that in the moral realm freedom is only a means whereby men can pursue their proper end, which is virtue, he did understand that in the political realm freedom is the primary end. If, with Acton, we "take the establishment of liberty for the realization of moral duties to be the end of civil society," the traditionalist conservative of today, living in an age when liberty is the last thought of our political mentors, has little cause to reject the contributions to the understanding of liberty of the classical liberals, however corrupted their understanding of the ends of liberty." (p.24)

    "We can no more make of the great conservative minds of the nineteenth century unerring guides to be blindly followed than we can condemn out of hand their classical liberal opponents. Sound though they were on the essentials of man's being, on his destiny to virtue and his responsibility to seek it, on his duty in the moral order, they failed too often to realize that the political condition of moral fulfillment is freedom from coercion.

    Signally they failed to recognize the decisive danger in a union of political and economic power, a danger becoming daily greater before their eyes as science and technology created apace immense aggregates of economic energy. [...] Looking to the state to promote virtue, they forgot that the power of the state rests in the hands of men as subject to the effects of original sin as those they govern. They could not, or would not, see a truth the classical liberals understood: if to the power naturally inherent in the state, to defend its citizens from violence, domestic and foreign, and to administer justice, there is added a positive power over economic and social energy, the temptation to tyranny becomes irresistible, and the political conditions of freedom wither.
    " (p.25)

    "In ultimate terms, upon the basic issue of human destiny, truths have been given us that we cannot improve upon, that we can only convey and make real in the context of our time." (p.25)

    "Power of a magnitude never before dreamed of by men has been brought into being. While separation of power has always been essential to a good society, if those who possess it are to be preserved from corruption and those who do not are to be safeguarded from coercion, this has become a fateful necessity under the conditions of modern technology. To the analysis of this decisive problem and to the development of political and economic solutions of it, classical liberalism contributed mightily. If we reject that heritage, we should be casting away some of the most powerful among our weapons against socialism, Communism, and collectivist Liberalism. The traditionalist who would have us do so because of the philosophical errors of classical liberalism, like the libertarian who rejects tradition because it has sometimes been associated with authoritarianism, seriously weakens the development of conservative doctrine." (p.26)

    "The economists of the liberal British tradition, from Adam Smith through and beyond the vilified Manchesterians, like the Austrian economists from Menger and Bohm-Bawerk to Mises and Hayek, analyzed the conditions of industrial society and established the principles upon which the colossal power that it produces can be developed for the use of man without nurturing a monstrous Leviathan. Without their mighty intellectual endeavor, we should be disarmed before the collectivist economics of Marx, Keynes, and Galbraith." (pp.26-27)
    -Frank Straus Meyer, "Freedom, Tradition, Conservatism", 1964, in Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.

    "That which is called liberalism today has deserted its heritage of defense of the freedom of the person to become the peculiarly American form of what in Europe is called democratic socialism. This transformation was the result of a fatal flaw in the philosophical underpinnings of nineteenth-century liberalism. It stood for individual freedom, but its utilitarian philosophical attitude denied the validity of moral ends firmly based on the constitution of being. Thereby, with this denial of an ultimate sanction for the inviolability of the person, liberalism destroyed the very foundations of its defense of the person as primary in political and social matters." (p.33)

    "The conservatives of the last century were sound in their fundamental philosophical position, upholding the objective existence of values based upon the unchanging constitution of being as the criterion for moral thought and action. They staunchly held the line against the assault of utilitarianism, positivism, and scientism; but on another level they failed philosophically, deeply misreading the nature of man. They would not or they could not see the correlative to their fundamental philosophical position: acceptance of the moral authority derived from transcendent criteria of truth and good must be voluntary if it is to have meaning; if it is coerced by human force, it is meaningless." (p.34)

    "We are told that what is not in the tradition of Burke-or of the medieval synthesis-or of Plato-cannot call itself conservatism: anyone who insists upon freedom in the political and economic sphere together with "legitimate" conservative beliefs is really half liberal, half conservative, a sad case of intellectual schizophrenia." (p.36)

    "Without something in the nature of an ideal image of what a good society should be, without an end which political action can strive to approximate, there is no basis for judging the rights and wrongs of the practical alternatives that constantly present themselves." (p.37)

    "The only equality that can be legitimately derived from the premises of the freedom of the person is the equal right of all men to be free from coercion exercised against their life, liberty, and property. This is the touchstone of a free society. For the rest, the capabilities of men, specific and inherited, should determine their position, their influence, and the respect in which they are held." (p.38)

    "I do not assume that reason is the sole possession of a single living generation, or of any man in any generation. I do assume that it is the active quality whereby men (starting with a due respect for the fundamental moral knowledge of ends and values incorporated in tradition) have the power to distinguish what ought to be from what is, the ideal from the dictates of power. Upon these assumptions, I shall attempt to reestablish, in contemporary contexts, principles drawn from the nature of man." (p.40)

    "The apprehension of man as of such a nature that innate freedom is of the essence of his being, is the central axiom upon which this critique of political thought is founded." (p.48)

    "They are, indeed, ideal principles and must be adapted in the light of the material situ~tion and the demands of conflicting interests. They will need to be made concrete in different ways under different circumstances." (p.48)

    "The art of politics at its best is guided by fundamental principle, but operates by judgment, by prudence. Both are necessary; without the guiding principles of political theory, based in turn upon fundamental philosophical considerations, the practical art of politics is without direction and soon becomes an exercise in expediency for expediency's sake." (p.49)
    -Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom: A Conservative Credo, 1962, in Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.




    _________________
    « La question n’est pas de constater que les gens vivent plus ou moins pauvrement, mais toujours d’une manière qui leur échappe. » -Guy Debord, Critique de la séparation (1961).

    « Rien de grand ne s’est jamais accompli dans le monde sans passion. » -Hegel, La Raison dans l'Histoire.

    « Mais parfois le plus clair regard aime aussi l’ombre. » -Friedrich Hölderlin, "Pain et Vin".

    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Admin


    Messages : 20741
    Date d'inscription : 12/08/2013
    Localisation : France

    Frank Straus Meyer, In Defende of Freedom and Related Essays Empty Re: Frank Straus Meyer, In Defende of Freedom and Related Essays

    Message par Johnathan R. Razorback Ven 10 Juil - 13:31

    "Social and political organization, however important as a condition of existence, is, like oxygen or water, a condition, not the end, of the life of the individual person." (p.50)

    "So far as the increased power of the state to bring evil to the individual is concerned, that power is directly proportional to the pretences the state makes to control men's lives for good. To the degree that the political theory upon which the state is founded regards political and social institutions not simply as a condition of human existence, but as the determining cause of the well-being of men, the more it becomes an active source of ill-being. This much one can concede as a twentieth-century gloss on the eighteenth-century couplet: the state can cause greater harm than then, but cure no more." (pp.50-51)

    "Our humanitarians of the welfare society take this as their maxim: treat no person as an end, but only as a means to arrive at a general good." (p.55)

    "Just as it shades off on the one hand into the platitudes of editorialists for "modern Republicanism" or the rhetoric of sated New Dealers in a mood to consolidate the Roosevelt revolution and sanctify it with a conservative aura, so on the other hand [New Conservatism] sometimes is confused with the very different approaches of such conservative analysts of political philosophy as Eric Voegelin, Leo Strauss, and Willmoore Kendall, or of such critics as Richard Weaver and Frederick Wilhelmsen." (p.60)

    "The European situation differs so sharply from the American that even those like Michael Oakeshott, who are closest to the attitudes of the New Conservatism, represent a rather different phenomenon." (p.61)

    "The refusal to recognize the role of reason, the refusal to acknowledge that, in the immense flow of tradition, there are in fact diverse elements that must be distinguished on a principled basis and considered in their relationship to present realities, is a central attribute of New Conservative thought.

    It is this which separates the New Conservatism from the conservatism of principle that rejects Burke and the Burkean approach
    ." (p.64)

    "The virtue of prudence, the faculty that adapts general principles to concrete circumstances." (p.64)

    "The dread of definition, of distinction, of clear rational principle is characteristic of the New Conservatism. [...] Rejection of the weapon of reason forecloses the possibility of a consistent and cogent attack upon the liberal-collectivist philosophy." (p.65)

    "It is true that abstract theoretical principles cannot be applied without consideration of circumstances, of the possibilities which in fact exist at a given time. That, however, does not mean that prudence can successfully function without the guidance of reason. It does not mean that because concrete circumstances affect the application of principle, they therefore replace principle and become the sole determinant of political theory." (p.66)

    "There is a dichotomy between historical experience as a theater in which men work out their drama and the transcendent standard of truth and good from which that drama takes meaning." (p.66)

    "The "freedom from" here deprecated is freedom in its true meaning. The "freedom for" is not freedom at all, but simply a set of ends conceived as the proper purpose of freedom. While the ends posited in this argument differ profoundly from those propounded by the New Conservatives ("freedom for" being usually conceived in terms of jobs, security, and the rest of the materialist Bill of Claims), this attitude reflects the same conceptual rejection of integral freedom. Neither the welfarestatist with his materialist ends nor the New Conservative with his spiritual ends is willing to accept freedom. The word, however, is a good word, a "God-term" in Richard Weaver's terminology ; and both make play with it. But neither is willing to face the conclusion that acceptance of freedom in its true meaning would force upon him: that freedom does not lead inexorably and of itself to the ends which either of them espouses, but only makes it possible for each individual person to choose between them." (p.74)

    "The mere fact that to exist man must live under some political order cannot be itself the standard by which the character of an order may be judged. The problem rather is what political order, in the circumstances of any given place and era, will best conduce to the establishment and preservation of conditions most favorable to the pursuit of the ends of man's existence.

    The New Conservative differs from the collectivist liberal as to the nature of these ends. He rejects the contemporary or thodoxy which is based upon the idea that man is but a toolbearing gregarious animal whose end is material welfare ; in the tradition of the West, he posits as the end of man the pursuit of
    virtue. Where he fails to differentiate himself, however, from those he opposes is in his acceptance of the idea that ends are implicit in the flux of experience. Whether that flux be thought of as materialist or Providential, and whether therefore the ends it dictates are material or ideal, both notions lead to the denial of the possibility of choice and freedom. And from this denial arises the concept of a political order where power rests of right in the hands of those who understand the true ends of existence, of those who can force men to be, in the one case, materially happy, in the other case, virtuous
    ." (pp.77-78)

    "Men cannot be forced to be free, nor can they even be forced to be virtuous. [...] Virtue is the fruit of well-used freedom. And no act to the degree that it is coerced can partake of virtue-or of vice." (p.78)

    "A good society is possible only when both these conditions are met: when the social and political order guarantees a state of affairs in which men can freely choose and when the intellectual and moral leaders, the "creative minority," have the understanding and imagination to maintain the prestige of tradition and reason, and thus to sustain the intellectual and moral order throughout society.

    To the degree that either of these conditions is lacking, a society will not be a good society, and the individual men who constitute it will suffer in their humanity. Granted the highest development of freedom in the political order, a failure of the responsible interpreters of the intellectual, moral, and spiritual
    order would make freedom a useless toy by depriving men of standards by which to guide their lives. On the other hand, given the most elevated intellectual, moral, and spiritual understanding, the subordination of the political order to the enforcement of that understanding, the denial to men of the freedom to accept it or reject it, would make virtue meaningless and truth rote
    ." (p.81)

    "The duties of human beings are not tribute owed to Leviathan; they are moral imperatives grounded in objective value. [...]
    Rights are moral claims which each individual person has upon other persons and upon all associations of other persons, including in particular the state; and they remain valid whether he is a good man or an evil man, whether he performs his duties or fails to perform them. Duties are obligations morally binding on each person, whatever his situation, whether other men, groups of men, or the state respect his rights or trample upon them. No man can give as an excuse for failure to carry out a duty that others have failed to respect his rights. No man, no group of men, no state, can give as an excuse for depriving an individual person of his inherent rights that he has failed to perform a duty. Duties and rights both derive from the same source, the moral ground of man's nature. But if they are made directly dependent one upon the other, they cease to be rights or duties. Losing their moral autonomy, rights become privileges dispensed to the individual by society or the state, and duties become obediences extorted by power as a payment for privileges. [...]
    The content remains the same-the right to live uncoerced by force or fraud in the possession of life, liberty, and property.
    " (p.83)

    "The paradox that to achieve this it is necessary in practice to restrain the freedom of individuals to interfere with other individuals is the reason for the state's existence. And the political order is to be judged, therefore, in terms of its success in dealing with this paradox of social existence, in terms of its preservation of the conditions of freedom." (p.84)

    "This inability to free themselves from the polis experienced as an organic being, of which individual men are but cells, was an omnipresent limit upon the genius of the Greeks in political-theoretical speculation." (p.92)

    "The philosophes of the Enlightenment are, equally with men of passion like Rousseau and St.:Just, creators of that cataclysm and of the deification of nation and state following from it." (p.95)

    "Those who possess the power of the state possess it exclusively and over against the rest of society, whether their power is confirmed by hereditary right, landed property, wealth, or the democratic ballot." (p.97)

    "States can be judged by the criteria by which all human institutions should be judged: their adequacy in their own sphere to the achievement of the best possible circumstances in which human beings may work out their destiny. From the primary problem of politics, the tension of freedom and order, we have drawn the principles for judgment of that adequacy: those principles demand a state capable of maintaining order while at the same time guaranteeing to each person in its area of government the maximum liberty possible to him short of his interference with the liberty of other persons." (p.98)

    "Some form of order is a human necessity. Without it, freedom itself is impossible. The state-that is, an institution recognized as the repository of legitimate violence to inhibit one man in his freedom from destroying another man's freedom-is therefore an institution called into being by the very nature of men's existence. It is a necessary and natural institution-so long as it fulfills its function and does not use its power for purposes extraneous to that function." (p.99)

    "When the state enters the economic sphere, when the state makes positive rules as to how men shall live that go beyond the preservation of the essential conditions of a free order, when the state takes upon itself the education of children or insurance against the hazards of life- with each of these steps its monopoly of force in the form of violence is fortified by control of economic, social, and ideological life. Step by step it amasses the decisive control of society. Each step makes the next one easier, and each step makes it harder to reverse the process. The state, from a natural and necessary institution in the social order, becomes a Leviathan, amassing to itself a decisive power that can only end in the destruction of the liberty of its citizens." (p.100-101)

    "The human mind cannot in fact function without philosophical principles, whether they are consciously arrived at and held or unconsciously and uncritically taken for granted." (pp.102-103)

    "It is possible in the span of a generation or two to eliminate such a middle class without terror or physical liquidation. Inheritance taxes, which eat away the substance of families who concern themselves not with the accumulation of money, but with carrying forward and developing the tradition of the civilization; a steeply graduated progressive income tax, which almost entirely inhibits the possibility of establishing an estate and founding a family free from the external pressures of society: these will in the space of a few decades destroy all independence, except that of a few very wealthy families. It is this process, which we have witnessed during the past thirty years, that has largely destroyed the classes which traditionally represented decisive public opinion, replacing them with the pliable mass public of today. [...] Tax to destroy the independent; spend to create the dependent; from the destruction of the one and the elevation of the other, maintain the power of the bureaucratic elite." (p.109)

    "Like all twentieth-century theories of the state, the liberal-collectivist theory is a variation on the Rousseauian concept of the state as the embodiment of the General Will." (p.115)

    "The concept of the deified will of the people furnished a quasi-moral justification without specific moral content, ready to be taken hold of by any "elite." Filled with whatever ideological content social circumstances and ideological predilections suggested to them, it was a tool well-adapted to be used, first to raise themselves to power, then to destroy their enemies, and finally to gain consent from the governed. These goals, particularly the last, could never have been reached under the aegis of the naked positivist glorification of power. The theory of the General Will in its various manifestations provided the necessary appearance of moral justification.

    The empty abstraction whereby the General Will was identified neither with the particular will of individuals nor of groups nor even of a majority, but with an assumed underlying real will of the totality, enabled each elite in turn to fill out the lineaments of the totality whose will was holy, in such a manner that this will became what the elite wished it to be. Consent was gained and moral rectitude affirmed by an identification of the totality with those whose consent was to be secured. The Volk of the Nazis, the proletariat of the Communists, are but manifestations of this totality whose will is the General Will, lay figures draped out to gain the consent of the masses. These figures are presented as if they were indeed the very image of the masses, but in reality they are only representations of the will of the elite: the will of the Communist Party is the true will of the proletariat; the will of the Fuhrer is the true will of the German Volk. (This is not simple hypocrisy. The leading Communist, the leading Nazi, deeply believes that he does embody the true will of the people, as the Jacobin leaders of the Convention, Rousseau's immediate heirs, believed they embodied the true will of the French Nation.)
    " (p.117)

    "To achieve a good society requires men unremittingly devoted to the pursuit of good and truth, but it requires also that no one have the power to impose beliefs by force upon other menand this whether those beliefs be false or true. It is clear why this is so if the beliefs are false; it is more difficult to see why this is still so if they are true. Why cannot state power, if held by governors imbued with true principle, be used to force virtue upon men ? Why should error not be forcibly destroyed ? The answer lies, as I hope what I have written has demonstrated, in the nature of man and of virtue. The only "virtue" that can be enforced would be a virtue that consisted in conforming one's behavior to external dictation." (pp.120-121)

    "Believing that "society is a spiritual entity," it becomes impossible for the New Conservatives to see the state as physical power in the hands of a specific group of human beings. It becomes impossible to understand that the state, though a necessity of human existence, has an unlimited potential for evil the moment its power increases beyond the strict necessities of its function." (p.125)

    "The Aristotle who wrote "... in order to be good one must be in a certain state when one does the several acts, i.e., one must do them as a result of choice and for the sake of the acts themselves" [Nicomachean Ethics 6.12.1144a] is forgotten." (p.127)

    "Freedom, though it is the end of political theory and political action, is not the end of men's existence. It is a condition, a decisive and integral condition, but still only a condition of that end, which is virtue. The New Conservatives are right when they insist that a consideration of men in society must come to grips with the problem of virtue. They are only wrong in demanding that that problem be solved by the exercise of political power." (p.127)

    "The West has always recognized, in the representative moments of its drive towards the incarnation of its vision, that the ultimate guardians of its essential truths could not be the possessors of material authority with their power to impose their own particular version of the truth and with their susceptibility to the corruptions of power. The guardians of intellectual and moral truth, to whom the West has always given its final deference (to the destruction of those who would impose an armored truth) have been the learned, the priestly, the prophetic, skilled in the traditionmen devoted to the priority of persons over institutions, devoted not to power, but to truth and good." (p.132)

    "If I inveigh against the concept of community as a decisive concept in political and social thought, or insist upon the priority of the individual person to collective groups of any sort, I am not therefore proposing a Robinson Crusoe social theory or maintaining that the person is a monadlike atom, cut off and isolated from other persons. These are the usual accusations brought by the proponents of community against the defenders of freedom. Again they propound a dilemma: Either accept the priority of community to the person or stand convicted of rejecting love, friendship, all mutual action and communion among human beings. But this time, too, the dilemma is unreal ; indeed, in this case it turns upon its framers. Only the independence and autonomy of the person makes love or any other valid relationship between persons possible." (p.133)

    "The family is the most important form through which virtue is inculcated in children. But it is not the institution of the family as such that inculcates virtue; it is the persons who constitute the family-father and mother and other close relatives- who in actuality decide the issue of the moral and intellectual direction that children take.

    So it is with the other institutions and associations into which men enter. It is not some mystical quality of "community" which makes these institutions and associations conducive to the growth of virtue. They will assist or impede that great human endeavor, depending upon their form; but the positive content of the endeavor will always arise from the beliefs, the understanding, the devotion of the individual persons who associate themselves. The form of institutions has no power to make bad men good or good men bad. They can, under circumstances of the kind we have seen too much of in this unhappy century, restrict freedom and undermine the responsibility of the individual so that they become a serious impediment to the growth of virtue; but they cannot, of their own power, make men good. At their best, they can create favorable conditions -and that is all.
    " (pp.135)

    "The doctrines of Lord Keynes, and of the heirs of Lord Keynes, lead directly to the siphoning off of a large proportion of the property of individual persons into the hands of the state. By that token, the power of the state is swollen, and the power of persons to stand firmly on their own, independent of the state and of the pressure of any collective influence, is progressively weakened; free citizens steadily deteriorate into wards of the state. The Keynesian system leads insensibly to "euthanasia" of the free energy of persons -in its end it parallels the Marxist system, different though its methods are. The welfare state -that is, the state that draws into itself function after function that belongs to individual men (provision for the eventualities of sickness, unemployment, accident, variations in market conditions; the education of children; responsibility for the care of aging members of the family: all the vicissitudes of life) is founded upon Keynesian and neoKeynesian doctrines. The ends towards which it moves are the security of the anthill or the beehive and the transformation of free men into a state-enforced similitude to the ants and the bees." (p.139)

    "Unless men are free to be vicious, they cannot be virtuous. No community can make them virtuous. Nor can any community force upon them conditions antagonistic to virtue if the state does not, with its power, give coercive strength to community and so long as the state, fulfilling its limited but necessary functions, protects individual persons from force and fraud by other persons and associations of persons.
    The person is the locus of virtue.
    " (p.148)

    "Freedom brings men rudely and directly face to face with their own personal responsibility for their own free actions. This is a shock. Remembrance of the fleshpots of enveloping security ever tugs insidiously at the souls of free men. But where mind and will have been clear and firm, the temptation has been rejected." (p.150)

    "The issue rests upon the question: can the new and rising conservative leadership release and guide the pent-up energies, the intuitive understanding of their heritage, the love of freedom and virtue in the hearts of the American people, before the converging forces of cloying collectivism at home and armed collectivism abroad destroy the very meaning of freedom ? That issue rests, as every important human issue always rests, in the hands of individual persons. [...] The decision hangs upon our understanding of the tradition of Western civilization and the American republic, our devotion to freedom and to truth, the strength of our will and of our determination to live as free and virtuous men." (p.151)
    -Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom: A Conservative Credo, 1962, in Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.



    _________________
    « La question n’est pas de constater que les gens vivent plus ou moins pauvrement, mais toujours d’une manière qui leur échappe. » -Guy Debord, Critique de la séparation (1961).

    « Rien de grand ne s’est jamais accompli dans le monde sans passion. » -Hegel, La Raison dans l'Histoire.

    « Mais parfois le plus clair regard aime aussi l’ombre. » -Friedrich Hölderlin, "Pain et Vin".

    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Admin


    Messages : 20741
    Date d'inscription : 12/08/2013
    Localisation : France

    Frank Straus Meyer, In Defende of Freedom and Related Essays Empty Re: Frank Straus Meyer, In Defende of Freedom and Related Essays

    Message par Johnathan R. Razorback Mer 15 Juil - 20:50

    "The arid subhuman image of man and the calculated cruelties of Ayn Rand." (p.157)

    "Lord Acton's insight still remains true, that there is in power a tendency to corrupt, and the more absolute the power, the more absolute the corruption. The experience of mankind has demonstrated this sad truth, however different may have been the. philosophical foundations of those who held power that approached the absolute. Diocletian and Constantine, Inquisitionist and Cromwellian, Nazi and Communist -all have exhibited the corruption that power brings in its train. Each had a vision of how men ought to live and was determined to force that vision upon those subject to their will. [...] If the state is endowed with the power to enforce virtue, the men who hold that power will enforce their own concepts as virtuous." (pp.157-158)

    "The denial of the claims of virtue leads not to conservatism, but to spiritual aridity and social anarchy; the denial of the claims of freedom leads not to conservatism, but to authoritarianism and theocracy." (p.162)

    "Neither virtue nor freedom alone, but the ineluctable combination of virtue and freedom is the sign and spirit of the West.

    The West is in decay not, as Mr. Bozell asserts, because "the free society has come to take priority over the good society" but because freedom has declined as virtue has declined. The recovery of the one demands the recovery of the other ; the recovery of both is the mission of conservatism today.
    " (p.163)
    -Frank Straus Meyer, "Why Freedom", National Review, 25 septembre 1962, in Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.

    "His fault is not in his conclusions, but in his mode of arriving at them. He did not understand the source of man's rights in the realm of value beyond history." (p.167)

    "The basis of Mill's defense of the liberty of the individual is unsound not because the liberty of the individual is anything less than the first (although not the only) political principle of a good society and certainly not because the victory of totalitarianism and welfarism in the twentieth century makes liberty an "outdated" ideal; it is unsound because the grounds of his defense, far from being too absolute, are not absolute enough." (p.168)
    -Frank Straus Meyer, "In Defense of John Stuart Mill", National Review, 28 mars 1956, in Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.

    "Conservatism, which in preserving the tradition preserves this truth, is only constant to itself when it is libertarian." (p.169)

    "The place of freedom in the spiritual economy of men is a high one indeed, but it is specific and not absolute. By its very nature, it cannot be an end of men's existence. Its meaning is essentially freedom from coercion, but that, important as it is, cannot be an end. It is empty of goal or norm. Its function is to relieve men of external coercion so that they may freely seek their good." (p.185)
    -Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.

    "Conservatism is not antirational. It demands only that reason operate upon the foundation of the tradition of civilization, that is, upon the basis of the accumulated reason, experience, and wisdom of past generations." (p.189)

    "Conservatism assumes the existence of an objective moral order based upon ontological foundations." (p.192)

    "Conservatives are opposed to state control of the economy in all its Liberal manifestations, whether direct or indirect. They stand for a free economic system for two reasons. In the first place, they believe that the modern state is politically so strong, even without controls over the economy, that it concentrates power to a degree that is incompatible with the freedom of its citizens. When to that power is added control over the economy, such massive power is created that the last defenses against the state becoming a monstrous Leviathan begin to crack. Second-though this is subsidiary in the conservative outlook to the danger to freedom-conservatives in general believe, on the basis of classical and neoclassical economic theory, that a free economy is much more productive of material wealth than an economy controlled directly or indirectly by the state." (p.195)
    -Frank Straus Meyer, "Conservatism", Reprinted from Left, Right and Center: Essays on Liberalism and Conservatism in the United States, ed. Robert A. Goldwin (Chicago: Rand McNally, for the Public Mfairs Conference Center, Kenyon College, Gambier, Ohio, 1967, in Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.

    "Le conservatisme n'est pas antirationnel. Il exige seulement que la raison fonctionne sur la base de la tradition de la civilisation, c'est-à-dire sur la base de la raison, de l'expérience et de la sagesse accumulées par les générations passées." (p.189)

    "Le conservatisme suppose l'existence d'un ordre moral objectif basé sur des fondements ontologiques." (p.192)
    -Frank Straus Meyer, "Conservatism", Reprinted from Left, Right and Center: Essays on Liberalism and Conservatism in the United States, ed. Robert A. Goldwin (Chicago: Rand McNally, for the Public Mfairs Conference Center, Kenyon College, Gambier, Ohio, 1967, in Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.

    "In the Hellenic civilization it was the philosophical movement culminating with Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle that raised to the level of consciousness this new understanding of the nature of men and their relations to ultimate things. The sense of the individual, the person as over against society, had been inherent in the ethos of the Greeks from the dim beginnings of Hellenic civilization. Such a sense is apparent already in Hesiod and Homer. It inspires the human scale of their archaic temples, as contrasted with the monstrous inhumanity of scale of ziggurat, pyramid, and sphinx." (p.212)
    -Frank Straus Meyer, "Western Civilization: The Problem of Political Freedom", Modern Age, Spring 1968, in Frank Straus Meyer, In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1996, 238 pages.



    _________________
    « La question n’est pas de constater que les gens vivent plus ou moins pauvrement, mais toujours d’une manière qui leur échappe. » -Guy Debord, Critique de la séparation (1961).

    « Rien de grand ne s’est jamais accompli dans le monde sans passion. » -Hegel, La Raison dans l'Histoire.

    « Mais parfois le plus clair regard aime aussi l’ombre. » -Friedrich Hölderlin, "Pain et Vin".


    Contenu sponsorisé


    Frank Straus Meyer, In Defende of Freedom and Related Essays Empty Re: Frank Straus Meyer, In Defende of Freedom and Related Essays

    Message par Contenu sponsorisé


      La date/heure actuelle est Dim 17 Nov - 16:30