L'Académie nouvelle

Vous souhaitez réagir à ce message ? Créez un compte en quelques clics ou connectez-vous pour continuer.
L'Académie nouvelle

Forum d'archivage politique et scientifique

Le Deal du moment :
Cartes Pokémon : la prochaine extension ...
Voir le deal

    János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács

    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Admin


    Messages : 20946
    Date d'inscription : 12/08/2013
    Localisation : France

    János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács Empty János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács

    Message par Johnathan R. Razorback Jeu 25 Avr - 14:32

    "In 1918, he became a committed Marxist and joined the Communist Party of Hungary, subsequently playing a role in the Hungarian proletarian dictatorship of 1919. After the collapse of the short-lived regime, he lived in Vienna, in Berlin and—from 1933 until 1945—in Moscow, assuming a variably active role (in the literary and political fi elds) in the work of the communist parties of Hungary, the Soviet Union and Germany. During his Moscow years, he became politically marginalized but in the shadow of the fascist threat he reluctantly agreed to a compromise with Stalinism. In 1945, he returned to Budapest where his participation in Imre Nagy’s government at the time of the 1956 revolution was to be his fi nal political role." (p.3)

    "His attempt to found the ontology of social being was considered by most, including his own disciples, to have been a failure. For example, shortly before his death, prominent members of the “Budapest School” (all of them his previous followers: Ferenc Fehér, Ágnes Heller, György Márkus, Mihály Vajda) had addressed to him an extensive critical comment on the unfinished Ontology of Social Being. Their article appeared in the leading Hungarian philosophical journal (Magyar Filozófi ai Szemle—Hungarian Philosophical Review), and some years later had been republished in English in a volume dedicated to the reappraisal of Lukács’s philosophy (Fehér et al. 1983). The notes made by the authors express a profound disagreement with most of the theoretical statements of Lukács. (They reject, among many other things, his interpretation of the fundamental category of “genericness” or “species being” and his distinction between “genericness-in-itself” and “genericness-for-itself”." (p.4)

    "A seemingly incidental footnote in History and Class Consciousness, which is nevertheless illustrative of Lukács’s exceptional intuition. In the footnote, the philosopher lays the foundations for a complete research program, based on some interesting observations made by Marx. The goal of the program would be to investigate in a systematic manner the interaction between language and society, departing from the hypothesis that the structures of reifi cation also penetrate language. This is a most radical interpretation of the social nature of language, for it implies the following: language is a social phenomenon not only in the general sense of it being a means for contact among people, but also in the specific sense that the given social relations (e.g., production and commodity relations) are inherently present in the linguistic forms themselves—in, for instance, the semantic structure of expressions. In other words, social relations are not simply “reflected” in language ; rather, they shape and determine its essential structures. In the passages quoted by Lukács, Marx refers to certain linguistic phenomena as “products of the bourgeoisie,” thereby clearly indicating that language has a class nature.

    Lukács does no more than mention the possibility of philological research from a historical materialist viewpoint. Even so, we have every reason to suppose that he considered it possible to extend the reifi cation theory expounded in History and Class Consciousness to linguistic phenomena. That is to say, the theory of reification has logical space for a general theory of language that would embody a systematic discussion of linguistic reification and linguistic alienation." (p.6)

    "In his later works, he dealt in far greater detail and more exhaustively with the language problem, doing so, however, on completely diff erent foundations. A reason for this may have been that during the rule of the Soviet version of Marxism, thinking about language was excessively infl uenced by the dispute over whether or not language should be considered one of the phenomena of superstructure. On one side of the argument were followers of the Georgian linguist Marr, who were convinced of language being an element of superstructure. On the other side was Stalin, who interfered in the linguistic debate and who adamantly denied the possibility of social relations infl uencing language in any way. (Stalin cut the Gordian knot when he stated that language “is neither ‘base’ nor ‘superstructure’.”) In his late major work on aesthetics, The Specificity of Aesthetic, Lukács himself went as far as to explain, in a naturalist fashion and based on Pavlovian physiological theory, that language is a second signal system (while also cautiously criticizing Pavlov for having ignored the role of work). In doing so, he abandoned the productive interpretation of the social nature of language, which he had proposed in History and Class Consciousness. Of course, this tied in with his renunciation of all concepts presented in his earlier great work.

    His final position was that the genesis and fundamental structure of language must be derived from labor. Based on this, as part of the social ontological concept laid out in his last work, he outlined a kind of ontological theory of language." (p.7)

    "The philosophy of science in the earlier work, similar to the references made to the class determination of language, is based on the theory of reification. This brings us to the fact that for Lukács the theory of science is first and foremost critique of science. And the manner in which he analyzes the effect of the structure of reification on the consciousness of classes indicates such central elements of his critique of science as, for example, the epistemological and methodological contrast between the natural sciences and the social sciences, the structural link between the natural sciences, capitalism and bourgeois class consciousness, or a definition of historical knowledge as self knowledge. The mere listing of these various factors shows that the Lukácsian critique of science was first and foremost a critique of positivism with roots going back to the pre-Marxian period of his work, to the German historicist, neo-Kantian, and Hegelian tradition.

    Here it is worth giving special mention to the scientific-theoretical dualism that is expressed in the juxtaposing of the natural sciences with the social sciences (e.g., with history). This is linked to the author’s subsequent condemnation—under the influence of dialectic materialism—of History and Class Consciousness, which was motivated by the fact that the book limits the validity of dialectics to society. Correct and truly scientific historical knowledge must be dialectic, for it removes itself from the rule (or control) of the scientific cognitive model, the extension of which to society is simply the projection of the structures of reification onto bourgeois consciousness. It is the inspection of the structure of reification that makes possible scientific knowledge of the whole of society, which, however, requires that we take the position of the class consciousness of the proletariat. Th is knowledge is also the self-knowledge of the proletariat. This kind of class determination of the nature and structure of knowledge renders recognition of some kind of proletarian science inevitable.

    After the consolidation of Soviet Marxism, a dogmatic belief—from the second half of the 1920s and into the 1930s—was that Marxist philosophy consisted of two parts: dialectic materialism and historical materialism. It was believed that the former described the general laws of objective reality (the “dialectics of nature”), while the latter applied these laws to special areas of society. It is understandable that the concept of History and Class Consciousness cannot be inserted into this formula in any manner. In The Specificity of the Aesthetic Lukács accepted the framework provided by dialectic and historical materialism, seeking to give structure to his work by means of a division into a general dialectic materialist part and a special historical materialist part. Of this, only the first part was completed, which explains the forms of consciousness, including the aesthetic form of consciousness, based on reflection theory.

    From a general philosophical perspective, the work bears many features of the dogmatism of Soviet Marxism. The same features are present—sometimes merely as annoying stylistic elements and sometimes at the level of content— in works by Lukács dating from the Moscow period and from the 1950s and 1960s. They are particularly apparent in The Destruction of Reason, which the philosopher published in the 1950s. In terms of their general philosophical foundations, therefore, the two works are closely linked. Typical of both is the subordination of the philosophical message to forceful political assumptions and objectives. The question is, to what extent does this influence today’s readers’ judgment of Lukács’s scientific, aesthetic and philosophical-historical arguments.

    At any rate, The Specifi city of the Aesthetic contains many beneficial innovations. These include the successful elaboration of a theory of everyday consciousness and the associated conceptual framework, which aid Lukács as he returns to the task of exploring the characteristics of scientific knowledge. In doing so, he focuses on the notion of de-anthropomorphization.

    The introduction of this new concept signifies the formulation from an original viewpoint of the requirement for objectivity in science, including the seemingly paradoxical motif that if this demand can be realized in the social and human sciences, then the latter must be just as de-anthropomorphized as the former ; that is to say, they too must disregard the fact that the subject of their investigation is a human phenomenon. In this way Lukács abandons scientific-theoretical dualism (and thus also the idea of a “proletarian” science) and accepts the program of a single unified science." (pp.8-9)

    "The neo-positivist movement that brought philosophy of science into being as a special discipline was still in its infancy, having recently been established by a group of philosophers belonging to the Vienna Circle (born just in 1922).

    There is no doubt that Lukács painted a picture of science that was wholly different from the ideas of these philosophers and which anticipated the approach that became typical in the post-neo-positivist period, as expressed in the works of such thinkers as Kuhn, Popper, Feyerabend, and Lakatos. It suffices to recall Lukács’s firm rejection of the kind of fact-fetishism represented by the positivism of his era with its idolizing of isolated facts unrelated to theory. A similar anti-empirical view was formed subsequently in the supposition concerning the theory-ladenness of facts and in the denial of a “theory-independent” empirical basis and of a neutral language of observation.

    Of course, we are not talking about a direct link, but rather of a relationship within a far broader tradition. Still, we may also assume a direct link, because Lakatos had been a student of Lukács in 1945 (indeed, one of his first pupils aft er his return in Hungary). Although we know little of substance about the relationship between the two men, there can be no doubt that the dialecticism imbibed from his master exerted a lasting effect on Lakatos’s thinking, and this is not even to mention the fact that his writings contain terms and concepts borrowed from Lukács.

    Perhaps the impact of such factors explains why, in the debate on scientific progress, Lakatos joined the critics of Kuhn. While he accused Kuhn, the theoretician of scientific revolutions, of irrationalism, he considered it important to emphasize that an acceptance of the rational nature of scientific progress aff ects our most fundamental intellectual, political and moral values." (pp.10-11)

    "From the outset Lukács employed a nuanced notion of rationality.

    On the one hand, he considered capitalism to be the mother of both rationalism and irrationalism. Based on the theory of reifi cation, he concluded that the partially rational nature of the various subsystems of capitalism (e.g., industrial production, bureaucracy, and specialized areas of science) inevitably come into conflict with the irrationality of the system as a whole. This remained throughout as a constant thought in his work, forming a bridge between the essays in History and Class Consciousness and the very different historical analyses contained in The Destruction of Reason. In the latter work, Lukács argues in a similar manner that the lack of transparency and “objective irrationality” of the social whole collide with the rationality of the separate systems of production and social organization and with the rationality of the now indispensable scientific research. The opaqueness of the global system of society and of the historical processes shaping it, gives rise to the objective impression that our life and history are unknowable and subject to blind forces.

    On the other hand, however, the partial systems emerging on the basis of their own logic are themselves fragile and limited. This means they can easily turn into their opposites and may also serve as fertile ground for ever renewable irrational philosophies.

    One should emphasize that The Destruction of Reason, a controversial late work, brought change both in Lukács’s own oeuvre and in Stalinism. Soviet Marxism, having been influenced by Lenin’s Materialism and Empirio-Criticism, considered the struggle between materialism and idealism to be its main organizing principle. In line with this, Lukács also thought in terms of a sharp dividing line between idealism and materialism. In contrast —as Alasdair Macintyre has demonstrated— it is extremely important that The Destruction of Reason is based on the antagonism between the rational and the irrational." (p.11)

    "It is not quite unfounded to say that there are two major trends in the 20th century: the analytics of language (the neo-positivists,Wittgenstein, ordinary language philosophers) and the hermeneutics of language (Heidegger and phenomenology on the one hand, and theFrench School represented by Ricoeur, Foucault and Lacan, on the other).

    It is natural to ask the question whether the problem of language had any place in the Marxist tradition. This is equivalent to the question whether the problem of language represented a philosophical problem for Marxism, and if so where its place is to be sought within the system of questions raised by Marxism.

    Lukács gives us a partial answer to these questions. And if we now focus our attention on Lukács, then it is worth considering another division in 20th-century philosophical thinking. Márkus György, a prominent member of Lukács’s circle of pupils (the “Budapest school”), distinguished two great philosophical paradigms: the “paradigm of production” and the“paradigm of language.” Whereas according to the former the paradigm of social objectivations is material production, the latter regards language and linguistic communication “as the universal paradigm of all forms of human intercourse and human objectivations” [...] Of course, from our perspective, the difference between these two paradigms is not that one of them has a place for language while the other has none, but that one describes language and linguistic communication as part of, and modeled on, other forms of activity, while the other considers language and linguistic communication to be the basis, or norm, of other forms of intercourse and other activities. Clearly, in this division, we must regard Lukács as an exponent of the production paradigm." (p.19)

    "The problem of the social nature of language is not exhausted in that it “only arises from the need, the necessity of intercourse with other men” (Marx 1998: 49).2 That is, it constitutes not only one aspect of the social nature of man in general, but it also includes the above connections, the intrusion of the historically concrete social structures and ideologies into the formal characteristics of language. And this has a decisive effect on consciousness, because consciousness is intimately linked to language. For this reason “consciousness is from the beginning a social product” (Marx 1998: 49), and there cannot be such a thing as “pure consciousness” (like the Kantian “reine Vernunft”), the reality of which was expressly denied by some great critiques of Kant, like Hamann and Herder, who had already pointed out the intrinsic relationship between language and consciousness. [...]

    The bourgeois can “prove from his language” the identity of “mercantile”and “general human aspects,” he can claim that the properties of the bourgeois individual are the human properties in general, because the ideology declaring this came to form, as it were, part of the linguistic code, and the linguistic code itself makes one accept the conceptual schemes anchored in it with a spontaneous naturalness. If it is added to the above that, as Marx emphasized, “ideas do not exist separately from language” (Marx 1973: 163) and that “the ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas” (Marx 1998: 67),3 then it is not without foundation that we attribute to Marx the view that the intellectual power of the ruling class constitutes linguistic power as well. This is the logical place for a critique of language and a philosophical analysis of language within Marxism. A criticism of ideologies necessarily involves a linguistic demystification based upon the comprehension of the connections between ideologies and language. When Lukács took heed of these ideas of Marx’s, he proceeded to formulate a highly important scientific program—well ahead of his time. The problems quoted have in the meantime been incorporated into the objectives of different disciplines concerned with language (semiotics, socio-linguistics, etc.), but what is called by Lukács “a philological analysis in the manner of a historical materialism,” and what ought to be understood as the historical investigation of the relationship between the dominant ideas of the various ages and their linguistic expression, has never been fully elaborated in the frameworks of Marxism." (pp.21-22)

    "It is easily discernible that there is a more or less elaborate conception of language contributing to the theoretical foundations of Lukács’s Aesthetics, and by virtue of its very role it claims to be more general and to grasp comprehensive tendencies of human language. At the same time, this conception reflects a radical change in Lukács’s scientific and philosophical orientation.

    It is an accident of history that the statements concerning language in Marxist philosophy were for decades influenced predominantly by a single discipline: Pavlovian physiology and psychology. This inevitably involved theoretical dogmatism (even if the rigid application of certain concepts in Pavlov had not by itself brought along naturalistic traits into the interpretation of linguistic phenomena), since the one-sided orientation to reflex theory excluded not only a generalization of the achievements of the other relevant disciplines, such as linguistics, but also an investigation into the logico-conceptual facet of the problem of language. Even Lukács could not help conforming to the contemporary situation of Marxism. That is why the conception of language in his Aesthetics displays as one of its most substantial constituents of Pavlov’s doctrine (which was developed by him into an original hypothesis of the intermediate “1’ signal system”).

    The unwary observer may have the impression that insofar as Lukács relies exclusively upon a single physiological doctrine while discussing the problem of language he comes to be opposed to not only his previous conception of the social nature of language but also to the whole of his philosophical and aesthetic ideas, in whose core lies Marx’s conception of the socio-historical nature of man. This is far from the truth as is best shown by the fact that although Lukács accepts without reservation Pavlov’s theory, he at the very outset subjects to criticism the tendency to examine the problems of the second signal system as abstracted from the wider implications of social practice and to take it as the basis of the interpretation of language.

    In doing so, it was obvious for Lukács to refer to Engels, who is known to have attributed a special role to labor in his explanation for the ape becoming man and for the emergence of language. It is worth quoting the following from Engels:

    [. . . ] the development of labour necessarily helped to bring the members of society closer together by increasing cases of mutual support and joint activity, and by making clear the advantage of this joint activity to each individual. In short, men in the making arrived at the point where they had something to say to each other. Necessity created the organ ; the undeveloped larynx of the ape was slowly but surely transformed by modulation to produce constantly more developed modulation, and the organs of the mouth gradually learned  to pronounce one articulate sound after another.

    Let us highlight two facets appearing in the paragraph: (i) labor is a jointly undertaken activity which has a socializing effect that results in people having “something to say” to each other; (ii) necessity created the vocal organ. The first facet implies a reference to the division of labor (although Engels does not use this word), while the second clearly contains a functionalist explanatory principle. (For our purposes, it is of course irrelevant which mechanism Engels thought had given rise to the vocal organ.) Both the argument concerning a link between labor, the division of labor and language and the functionalist explanation referring to a specific necessity have distinguished  theoretical historical roots, and these will be worth returning to later on.

    But first let us see how Lukács plays the Engels card against Pavlov:

    Pavlov’s statements must of course be always understood and interpreted in the sense of dialectical materialism. For however essential Pavlov’s second signal system may be from the point of view of discriminating between man and animal, its true sense, and its highly fruitful significance will be manifest only if, like Engels, we sufficiently stress the simultaneous rise of labor and language, their objective inseparability. Man’s having something to say, a fact which is beyond the sphere of the animal kingdom, originates directly in labor and unfolds—directly or indirectly, and later through a good deal of mediation—in correspondence with the development of labor.

    From a critical point of view even more unambiguous is the remark which demurs against the confusion of psychic phenomena in man and animal (in fact, image and concept in animals):

    Our objection, or rather, our supplementary proposal can be summarized as follows: Pavlov is in the right when stating that the second signal system and actual thought in terms of concepts are inseparably interrelated, upon which all scientific thought is based. But he does not even hint at the interrelation of the second signal system, speech, and labor. Pavlov is never concerned with historical and genetic questions. He is content to state the interrelation of the development of man and speech. [. . . ] The lack of the genetic link between labor and speech, since it is a very important interrelation, blurs to some extent the fact that the second signal system is a special human manner of apprehension and expression.

    The objection is all the more legitimate since by exploring the mechanismof reflex activity Pavlov not only endeavors to explain the physiological components of speech and thought, but he also believes to have grasped their specific essence. Lukács, contrarily, points out that for explaining the nature of language and thought it must be taken into account that they are the interiorizations of the specific human activity that constitutes their basis both in a historico-genetic and in a structural sense.

    We cannot ignore the degree of ambiguity in Lukács’s position. At times he speaks of “the simultaneous rise of labor and language,” while at others he claims that language arises directly from labor and emerges in tandem with the development of labor. This latter claim (like Engels’ own hypothesis) could only be verified in the light of a detailed evolutionary mechanism. All of this does not alter the fact that an investigation of language as a form of activity that is part of labor, has illuminative power. Today, it is easy to see this, as several theories put forward in recent decades point in a similar direction. This does not mean that we should conflate the different approaches and the various terms they use: labor, labor process, “teleological positing,” intentionality, and intentional action. (Of course, we are thinking here of those theories that give priority to the communicative function of language, such as the theory of linguistic action or the theory of communicative action. Of less salience are theories giving primary emphasis to the role of language in the expression of thought, such as the Chomskyan philosophy of language.)

    Lukács’s critique of Pavlov can be seen as a first tentative formulation of his later theory of language, according to which language and labor are categories of the same ontological level inasmuch as they bridge natural and social being: “Just like labor, language also represents a leap from natural to social being.” In the light of this we need a new kind of linguistics “that would take as its object of research or methodological guide the really existing connections between labor and speech,” and therefore, “could broaden and deepen our knowledge of the historical process of this leap.” (Lukács 1978: 3, 102)

    In accordance with this view, when describing the essential features of language (as well as when discussing the aesthetic sphere as a whole), Lukács makes use of the principle that a phenomenon can be understood in its entire depth only if we consider the genesis and the tendencies of development of the totality to which the phenomenon in question specifically belongs. That is why there are numerous references to ethnography on the pages devoted to the discussion of the essential features of language. The remarks on “primitive languages” are intended to illustrate the idea that the property that, according to Lukács, counts as the essential feature of language and which is some kind of “twofold motion,” that is, “overcoming the limits of the actual immediacy by means of generalization and the retransformation of the result thus achieved into a new, more comprehensive immediacy of higher power and better differentiation,” is at the same time the law of real history, of the real development of language. Thus the problem which submerged with Pavlov onto a mere physiological level ascends into historical dimensions, notwithstanding the fact that the data Lukács cites from Lévy-Bruhl and others can hardly be interpreted unambiguously. “If we observe the language of a primitive people chosen at discretion, we shall realise that their derivation of words is incomparably closer to perception and farther from concept than ours,” states Lukács on the assumption that primitive languages are capable of naming sensually concrete objects only and have no means to express the concept of genus. Now the considerations that start out from the assumption that primitive languages have no concepts for genus ascribe an exaggerated significance to a single aspect of language. To put it more exactly, they compare “civilized” and “primitive” languages from a single aspect: on the basis of lexical characteristics. It is doubtful whether this leads to a correct typology.

    Incidentally, considerations like the ones mentioned above served for Lévy-Bruhl as arguments for the justification of the existence of some “pre-logical”primitive mentality, which, as it were, should correspond to an infantile level of thought. This conception queries the universality of the basic course of human thought (prevalent even among the various kinds of the concrete socio-historical characteristics) and, in the last analysis, the uniformity of the human species, which contributed greatly to the legitimate criticism of structural and functional ethnology in this connection. As regards our basic problem it is, however, far more important to note that the facts described by Lévy-Bruhl do not constitute conclusive evidence. Boas was already able to demonstrate that the examples used to illustrate that the “concrete” nature of the “primitive languages” radically different from European languages are not generally valid: there exist primitive languages which, in spite of our scientific superstitions, abound in abstract terms which are also used as expressions of concepts for genus (Boas 1911: 657).

    This may well raise doubt as to the well-foundedness of some of the theoretical statements on language in Aesthetics but it does not exert a fatal effect on the evaluation of the substantial part of Lukács’s position, nor does it hinder, in some degree, the acknowledgment of the concrete linguistic relevance of these very statements. In sum, Lukács regards it as the general trend in the development of language that “linguistic forms reflecting concrete objects gradually disappear from language and are replaced by much more general common nouns.” He continues to say that from this it does not follow that “language loses the ability to concretely designate every concrete object,” since “in our relation to the world sentences acquire an increasing significance” [. . . ] “the complicated syntactic relations of the words determine their senses more and more in the concrete contexts of their application,” and “by virtue of the relations of the words arranged in sentences more and more sophisticated linguistic devices come into being for the purpose of demonstrating concrete objective relations.” Minimally one of the presuppositions of these statements is false, viz., that at the earlier stages of language development, thus in primitive languages, sentences had less significance and they turned into being a more and more essential element of linguistic activity “as it were” simultaneously with the eclipse of the words having concrete meaning." (pp.22-26)

    "Another point on which one must disagree with Lukács is that the ability to concretely designate objects was previously based on the semantic properties of words (on the concrete perceptual nature of their meaning). Leibniz—whom, incidentally, Lukács himself cites—demonstrated (in his polemic with Locke) that words can a priori be nothing but general. General terms are not incidental facts of language or facts occurring merely at certain stages of historical development. As Leibniz puts it, they “do not merely improve languages but are required for their essential structure.” It is thus, logically, impossible for words taken in themselves to relate to individuals. In Leibniz’s parlance “particular things” can be spoken of on this level only if “species (logically) infimae” are understood by them [...]

    At the same time, it should be made clear that sentence construction is an essential property of linguistic activity. According to the standard conception, accepted by almost all authoritative linguists, the fundamental unity of language is the sentence, that is, men speak in sentences at whatever stage of linguistic development. Still, the main problem is clearly Lukács’s view of the development of language, which Ferenc Fehér, one of the philosopher’s closest pupils, put down to the “overall tendency of evolutionism.” Fehér severely criticizes his master and shows that the application of the general scheme of evolutionism to language is unacceptable to all linguistic and psychological theories that are perceived as relevant (Fehér 1983: 104). Indeed, there is general agreement today that a concept of development extendable to language does not exist, as there is no criterion that could be used to distinguish between existing and known dead languages in terms of their “level of development.”

    We should note that Lukács is not completely consistent when committing himself to a kind of “linguistic evolutionism,” for he evidently did not think that concepts of development were valid in every field. We are quite aware that he accepted, for instance, Marx’s “Homer paradox,” namely that the classical works do not constitute a developmental sequence and that, on the contrary, such peaks of world literature as the Homerian epics arose in the earliest stages of social development and could not have arisen in any other period.

    Let us return to the issue of the extent to which the presence of complex syntactic structures realized in sentences is a part of each phase of the development of language. It seems we may say that—granting that language has a general trend of development at all—this comes to the fore not in the increase of the significance of sentences but in the increasing complication of sentence structure. Lukács’s statements quoted above can be accepted only if this is meant by them. All that is, however, is a psychological rather than a linguistic problem.

    Despite their problematic nature, in a roundabout way, Lukács’s statements are meaningful and that is why they do have scientific relevance. Note that what Lukács tackles is the problem of reference and singular description. In this connection he attains, with the informal means of philosophical analysis, the same results which can be achieved through a logical and grammatical analysis of linguistic structures. In his view, reference (the function of designating concrete objects) is not a separate relationship between the sign and the signified but a function of the relations within the sentence.

    Although expressions are a priori in general, individual objects can be grasped by linguistic means, which are provided for by syntax: among the conditions of singular description we find rules which are clearly syntactic. To put it more generally: the relationship of concrete reality and language is not only a semantic but also a syntactic problem. “Only an advanced syntax can designate individuality by means of the linguistic reproduction of ostension,” claims Lukács in the chapter on reproduction of his Ontology of Social Being.

    It is trivial, though perhaps not needless, to recall that the theory of language in The Specificity of the Aesthetic is related to the theory of everyday thinking. Lukács himself calls attention to the inherent relationship between the two problems: “The peculiarities of everyday thinking could perhaps be expressed most successfully if speech were subjected to a thorough analysis from this specific angle.” The central core of the problems of Aesthetics is thus occupied by ordinary language and this is an important fact. If a philosophy of language is viable at all it can set its foot at nothing but ordinary language, for—as is shown by Lukács himself—the sign systems carrying higher mental objectivizations emerge from the tendencies extant in ordinary language ; similarly, these higher mental objectivizations are themselves built upon the general foundation of everyday life and everyday thinking in order to constantly enrich this foundation with their results.

    If by abstraction we consider solely the topic we touched upon here, placing ordinary language in such a central position may relate Lukács’s theory of language to ordinary language philosophy, even if otherwise Lukács is strongly opposed to the views of the neo-positivist and analytical philosophers on the objectives and the very nature of philosophical research. Notwithstanding their methodological position, according to which important logical distinctions can be discovered by exploring the rules of the use of our linguistic tools, and by doing this we may get closer to understanding the conceptual frames determining thought, would have certainly deserved more attention from the part of a thinker who was investigating the structures of everyday thought." (pp.26-28)

    "Lukács not only rejected the views and methods of the analytical philosophers but also was rather perplexed by them. We see this in his chapter on Wittgenstein in The Ontology of Social Being. Here Lukács interprets several enigmatic sentences in Tractatus as “an involuntary excursion into the fi eld of onthology” (Lukács 1976: I. 73), merely acknowledging that, in terms of the present social condition, Wittgenstein does express something important and contradictory, namely the thinking and sentiments of those who, faced with the general manipulated nature of life, are incapable of anything but an inevitably impotent protest—the silence of Wittgenstein [...]

    It is worth paying heed to a few points within Lukács’s description of ordinary language, especially to the dialectical contradiction which, according to Aesthetics, is the central organizing principle of the problems arising here. One of the aspects of this contradiction is that language is the substantial property of the mind (“the practical mind itself”), as regards its functioning, the movement of its structures, it is unconscious. Th is point is expressed by Lukács in another way: by means of the category of “mediation,” but owing precisely to this category he goes beyond a simple description of the paradox in question: “people necessarily relate to speech immediately, though as regards its nature it is a system of more and more complicated mediations.”

    Through such an application of the category of mediation the problem of language is placed in the light of the comprehensive properties of human life activity. According to this, any new achievement involves a higher complication of determinations and a further articulation of the social conditions of life, and at the same time it becomes a “natural,” spontaneously manifest element of activity and thought extremely simplifying the relations of people to the world and one another. It is here that the source of the further aspects of the dialectical contradiction stressed by Lukács lies: it is the spontaneous naturalness of language that makes available all that is not immediately given to us, and the very same spontaneous availability hampers the “unbiased take-in” of the world. Th is last remark refers to a problem which is not examined by Lukács in detail, but to which he undoubtedly ascribes due significance. It can be summarized as follows: the structures of language influence the course of cognition in a defi nite direction. Another momentum or rather consequence of the same contradiction are the two contrary tendencies infl uencing the whole dynamics of ordinary language, which are called by Lukács, in a metaphorical phrase, though rather accurately, “the tendencies towards rigidity and plasticity.”." (pp.28-29)
    -János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács, Palgrave Macmillan, 2014, 144 pages.


    _________________
    « La question n’est pas de constater que les gens vivent plus ou moins pauvrement, mais toujours d’une manière qui leur échappe. » -Guy Debord, Critique de la séparation (1961).

    « Rien de grand ne s’est jamais accompli dans le monde sans passion. » -Hegel, La Raison dans l'Histoire.

    « Mais parfois le plus clair regard aime aussi l’ombre. » -Friedrich Hölderlin, "Pain et Vin".

    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Admin


    Messages : 20946
    Date d'inscription : 12/08/2013
    Localisation : France

    János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács Empty Re: János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács

    Message par Johnathan R. Razorback Jeu 7 Nov - 12:37

    "The following question arises at this point: insofar as thought indeed presupposes language and insofar as the structures of the diff erent human languages indeed determine thought, how is the universality of cognition possible ? In answering the question much can be gained from a study of linguistic productivity. Lukács is not concerned with the linguistic or technical side of the question but it amounts to no exaggeration to say that the signifi cance of the conception of language in Aesthetics consists in stressing the tendencies mentioned above. And grasping these tendencies fi xes a tie between the problems of ordinary language, on the one hand, and those of the sign systems carrying higher objectivizations: scientific and artistic language, on the other. It is to be expected on the basis of the discussion outlined in the foregoing that a number of important categories in Lukács’s Aesthetics are connected to considerations of the theory of language and that—conversely—certain categories will induce questions concerning the theory of language. For example, this is the case with the differentiation between the “whole man” and the “whole of man” (“Das Menschenganze”) or with the interpretation of “unconscious.” However, within the problems of the theory of language in Aesthetics, the central place is undoubtedly occupied by the hypothesis of the “first and second signal system.”." (pp.29-30)

    "Judging from the viewpoint of psychology the hypothesis is rather doubtful. Th us, the only sensible question to ask is what problems the introduction of the concept of the first and second signal system would have been evoked to solve and whether the phenomena Lukács wishes to account for by means of this concept are indeed important from the point of view of our general problem of language. In this case, Lukács’s hypothesis must by all means be regarded as a basis for discussion and a conception worthy of further contemplation even if otherwise it ought to be discarded as a scientific explanation. It is reasonable to assume that later on Lukács himself considered his ideas about the first and second signal system in a similar way. In the chapter on reproduction in the Ontology of Social Being we find the following: “Subtlety increases in speech and in listening, and in my Aesthetics I called it the sphere of the knowledge of man (the correct knowledge of the individual partner) and I used the expression ‘1’ signal system’  to denote its organ." Thus not even Lukács claims that this concept describes some kind of psychic reality, rather he holds it to be the name of a problem, a metaphorical circumlocution of a set of phenomena.

    Paradoxically, as early as in Aesthetics the hypothesis of the “1’ signal system” is expounded in a way which goes beyond a simple elaboration of Pavlov’s doctrines.

    Moreover, though Lukács modestly speaks of a “supplementary proposal,” he clearly starts from the recognition of the weakness of the explanatory power of Pavlov’s refl ex theory with respect to the phenomena he was mainly interested in. For the division according to the paired categories of the first and the second signal systems cannot comprise the totality of specific human utterances. According to the logic of this division, any response that cannot at all or can only defectively be verbalized counts as a simple conditioned reflex; consequently, the specific human nature of the specific psychic quality inherent in these responses will become inapprehensible. The fact that the “1’ signal system” is created to fill in that blank space is best evidenced by Lukács’s lucid critical comments, one of which will be quoted below. Pavlov recounts a case of aphasia, a patient who completely lost his ability to speak after a fit of epilepsy but could make himself understood by means of drawings. Pavlov judges the case to be an example of a possible separation of the first signal system from the second. The assessment shows that Pavlov considers non-verbal messages as the operation of the first signal system. He seems to assume also that the second signal system is simply added to the first in man, that is, he does not look upon the two planes of signals as an organic whole within which the lower plane is rendered under the higher one and undergoes a substantial structural change compared to the refl ex activity in animals. Lukács unequivocally asserts the doubtfulness of this view: “The drawing of an object —in contradiction to Pavlov— can in no wise be conceived as conditioned reflex. If the word ‘tree’ must be interpreted as a signal of signals, then the tree drawn in the same manner contains the generalizing apprehension of the tree immediately perceived which in its immediacy elicits unconditioned or conditioned reflexes.”

    It should be clear from the examples that Lukács’s hypothesis had a number of justifiable motives and the considerations underlying it have contributed to an overall specification of the problem of language. This specification takes into account not only a few conspicuous forms of linguistic activity but is based on a comprehensive view of the relevant phenomena. Today, however, these phenomena can be accounted for far more successfully by means of the conceptual apparatus of linguistics (for instance, by demonstrating the coding of paralinguistic elements), the devices of communication theory, psycho- and socio-linguistics, or the creation of a general semiotic framework.

    While analyzing the dialectics of the conscious and unconscious, Lukács points out that in the dynamic structure of ordinary language the most general characteristics of human practice and social development are expressed [...] In this respect language is not only a system of signs, an external mediator of internal psychic contents but is the category of practice in a definite sense." (pp.30-31)

    "Marxist works on language, in general, have not raised the question to what extent this infl uences the formal representation of language. With no respect to whether and what extent Lukács’s analyses can be made to correspond to the formal models of language, the theoretical connection between language and practice marks the point which separates a Marxist conception of language from the traditional positions. This is where Ontology of Social Being takes up the thread of analysis:

    Such an analysis of the continuity of social being will necessarily lead us to language as an important complex developed within this complex of social being.

    Thus, the problem of language is raised by the analysis of social being itself, and language as such must be construed as a complex within social being, one connected to the sphere of social existence. This gives rise to the most general definition of language:

    Language is the organ and medium of the continuity realized in social being.

    However simple and self-evident this definition may be, assuming its central position in the theory sheds new light upon the whole problem of language. For the tradition of linguistics and philosophy has placed the definition of language as the instrument of thought and communication in the center. This definition, no doubt, is correct, though it needs further elaboration since it does not contain, not even in an abstract manner, references to social needs developed through history which language must in the first place satisfy. Now, in Lukács’s opinion, every kind of explanation for language presupposes —in accordance with the “paradigm of production”— the knowledge of these needs, which emerged from the most general structure of social being. Logically, the category of reproduction allows for a detailed account of these problems." (p.32)

    "Such a change in the logic of the question has the consequence that the theory of the nature and genesis of language must form a unifi ed theory at least on the most general level, and this must be thought of as a general semiotic framework which provides an outlook on the problems of animal communication alongside with human communication.

    What was said in the foregoing also makes it possible for the significance of the relationship of labor and language to be presented in a more comprehensive way. Labor is not only the driving force of the genesis of language but also the explanatory principle for the structural characteristics of language. In other words, what should be noted in Lukács’s work is not simply that the historical occurrence of labor accounts for the historical occurrence of language but that the structures of language continually embed into the structural relations of the labor process. Note in this connection Lukács’s remark that the tendency towards “species being” (“Gattungswesen”), which objectively emerges from the structure of labor, “develops further” in language. Th at is, since “the most ordinary words express the generality of the object, the genus or the species, and not the individual instance, ...  the objective intention of language is directed ab ovo to the regularity of the subject, to the objectivity of the object designated by it.” Incidentally, it is worth noticing that contrary to some of his earlier remarks Lukács regards the striving for generality and the objectivity of the object as an ab ovo tendency of language. Th at “it is linguistically impossible to find a word that defines unambiguously the individuality of some object” is tantamount to saying that it is a logical property of language independent of factual and historical circumstances. According to Leibniz’s account, individuality can be approached but cannot be attained through the most concrete possible designation of the species. Th us particularity will serve as the special sphere of the linguistic expression endeavoring to grasp individuality. As has been shown, the act of referring, in which concrete objects are referred to and which involves the application of proper names or singular descriptions, is a function not of the concreteness of meanings but of “advanced syntax.”

    The connection of the structural characteristics of language and the basic structure of labor-activity is with Lukács not equivalent to stating some kind of isomorphic correspondence. Besides the structural interrelations shown in this context, Lukács also stresses the autonomy of language, which is expressed (in the phraseology of his categories) by stating the essential difference between labor and language with respect to the orientation towards “species being” as well as establishing the relationship of the individual and the general. Th e basis of the necessary generality of language is the fact that prior to any act of cognition, labor is itself an objective process of generalization. In labor, however, whatever is merely particular is eliminated so that the “objectively optimal,” the “species being” should have preference, whereas, according to the above, language must have the tendency toward individualization besides (and on the strength of) generalization. Moreover, “the more the original community of purely particular individuals changes to a community of personalities, the more linguistic expression must tend to individualize.”." (pp.32-33)

    "When commenting on this statement, we can call attention to an interesting methodological principle. Lukács clarifi es the logical properties of language, such as the ability to express the general and the individual, starting from the social relations of people and their communities, thus he is not content to emphasize merely cognitive aspects. Another point of importance as regards the problem touched upon here is that the structural determination of language by labor, on the one hand, and the autonomy of the logical structure of language, on the other, can be understood from the teleology of labor.

    Yet this is not tantamount to explaining the nature and genesis of language on the basis of a general teleological world view. All that is at stake here is merely that the objective teleological structure inherent in labor, which is also the basis of all subjective teleology, creates for men the possibility and the necessity of “having to say something to each other.”

    Incidentally, one should note that when addressing the connection between language and labor, Lukács does not concern himself with theoretical historical questions (other than, of course, his inevitable citing of Engels’ hypothesis). Here it is nevertheless worth pointing out the strength of the tradition says that language is first and foremost an activity (or, as Humboldt said, energeia rather than ergon) and, as such, can be linked with labor or more precisely with work activities that use tools. The main elements of this view can already be found in Plato’s Cratylus where Socrates, in the debate on the natural or arbitrary character of names, cites two arguments that are of particular interest to us. The first we can call an argument rooted in the actional nature of speech, while the second we may call an argument drawn from the instrumental nature of naming. The former implies that “speech and naming are a kind of action,” whereby we cannot act how we wish, because the actions “have a special nature of their own.” The second argument is based on the idea that “a name is an instrument,” like the awl or the shuttle, and that the naming of things, like the use of instruments and tools, has a correct or “natural” mode or fashion [...] The argument reflects recognition that speech and the proper use of a given tool are activities requiring the same logic, which, together with the immanently associated aims, are equally defi ned by objective and valid norms. (It is almost self-evident that we should compare the quoted Platonic passage with the words of Wittgenstein: “Think of the tools in a tool-box: there is a hammer, pliers, a saw, a screw-driver, a rule, a glue-pot, glue, nails and screws. Th e functions of words are as diverse as the functions of these objects.”." (p.34)

    "Among further examples —which can be listed right up until the 20th century— the most important is without doubt the Hegelian concept relating to the structural homology of logical inference and labor. Th e importance of the concept stems in part from the historical signifi cance of its own and in part from its extraordinary effect on Lukács’s thinking. One need only recall the insight that the same process of externalization is underway in language as in labor :

    The speaking mouth, the working hand, and, if you like, the legs are too the organs of performance and actualization which have within them the action qua action, or the inner as such. But the externality which the inner obtains through them is the action as a reality separated from the individual. Speech and work are outer expressions in which the individual no longer keeps and possesses himself within himself, but lets the inner get completely outside of him. (Hegel 1977: 187)

    As an example from the twentieth century one might cite Ernst Cassirer’s conception that the features of occupational or professional languages also tell us something of the origins of the language, as the inevitable link of expert languages with the division of activities illustrates the general embeddedness of language in action (Cassirer 1923: 255).

    The most interesting example, however, is to be found in Dante, who gave, in his De Vulgari Eloquentia, a strikingly original interpretation of the myth of the Tower of Babel and the confusion of tongues. Whereas before the fall of the tower the people doing the various tasks had all spoken one language and had worked well together, aft er its collapse languages emerged according to the various occupations.

    Only each group that had been working on one particular task kept one and the same language: for example, one for all the architects, one for all the stone-movers; for all the stone-cutters; and so on with every trade. And now as many languages separated the human race as there were different kinds of work. [...]

    Thus, it is beyond doubt that Dante explained the plurality of languages in terms of the division of labor.

    Since this explanation had no antecedents at the theoretical level, we may suppose that the poet based it on his own life experiences, for he lived in a world where the general cultural and linguistic eff ects of the nascent capitalist division of labor could already be felt. The translators of an earlier German version of the work refer to this when commenting on the place in question: “During the period, a Florentine would not have been surprised  by Dante’s idea that the languages of the nations could be traced back to the various artisan guilds” [...] Another excellent commentator on Dante showed how in Florence it was easy to recognize the differences of dialect and the links between the types of work performed in the various guilds [...]

    Since work is a jointly undertaken activity requiring coordination at group level, the notions of labor and the division of labor are inseparable. Any teleological act that can be said to be complete or accomplished is, indirectly or directly, a chain of multiple individual acts.

    Just as division of labor is inbuilt into the very structure of working activity (that is, in the case of humans the division of the activity is not genetically fixed), so are the realization of singular teleological relations and the articulation of the global objective of the total activity on group level all along interrelated. Thus humans transcend the animal property that the individual members of a species all “know” the same (or, in Lukács’s words, the reproduction of the species takes place within a world “known” in the same way)." (pp.35-36)

    "Social reproduction is subject to quite diff erent laws. Individuals do not “know the same things”: their knowledge and experience is highly differentiated and depends on their place in the spontaneous or institutional division of labor. Th is is the point where we can make a connection to Lukács and extend the inquiry he launched to a study of those functions and phenomena that are peculiar to language, such as meaning, understanding, communicability, and expressibility.

    There are several theories that one may not only link with the Lukácsian concept of language but also use to supplement or develop it. The most important of these theories are Hilary Putnam’s hypothesis on the division of linguistic labor (Putnam 1975b) and the Marxist semiotic conception of Ferruccio Rossi-Landi." (p.36)

    "Putnam introduces the term division of linguistic labor as a means of responding to the question of the relationship between linguistic meaning and our knowledge of the world.

    This question has been a recurrent topic of the mentalist concepts of meaning since the 17th century. Can we assume that the meaning of a word is the speaker’s experience or knowledge about the thing the word signifies ? As is known, this was Locke’s theory. He supposed that the word ‘gold’ has different meanings (stands for a diff erent “idea”) for those for whom gold is defined as a bright and heavy substance, for those who regard it a yellow moldable material and for those for whom it is a tensile substance. From this hypothesis follows that, as a word has different meanings for different speakers, we do not understand each other. So should not we think instead that the meaning of a word is the complete concept of a thing, which is the same for all speakers who otherwise have diff erent experiences? Consequently, the meaning of a word would include bits of information that the single speakers do not have concerning the thing they are speaking about. As is also known, this is Leibniz’s theory. Th ough this suggests that it can be easily the case that we do not understand even ourselves, Leibniz’s intention is farther reaching than that of Locke’s. And when Putnam examines the concept of the division of linguistic labor he follows an intuition very similar to Leibniz’s idea. According to him the meaning of ‘gold’ also includes what the speaker does not know about ‘gold’, but someone else, experts for example, might know about it. His conception is to be understood as follows.

    It is the division of linguistic labor that makes mutual understanding possible despite the diff erences in our knowledge about and experience of things. For the knowledge presupposed by language is possessed collectively by the members of a society. Even if we know the objects from diverse aspects and in diff erent depths, it is suffi  cient to identify our culture’s important objects by the help of words and to know the rules of using them. Only experts need to understand the complete meaning of words. And the ideal experts, whose competence represents the sum of the individual competencies, are entrusted with the knowledge of the totality of the linguistic system.

    This conception presupposes that division of linguistic labor is one of the forms of division of labor in general (or, as Putnam puts is, forms of mundane division of labor engender a division of linguistic labor; Putnam 1975b. So not only the general attributes of work (“live”, “stored-up”, “energeia” and “ergon”) can be applied to the language but also the concept of the division of labor that renders communication possible.

    The division of linguistic labor was introduced into the philosophy of language by Putnam as a socio-linguistic hypothesis. The novelty of the hypothesis was not the discovery that the knowledge and the use of language have a structure similar to the division of labor. It is original because of the observation that the division of labor is the essential nature of language. As Putnam says:

    The features that are generally thought to be present in connection with a general name—necessary and sufficient conditions for membership in the extension, ways of recognizing if something is in the extension (“criteria”), etc.—are all present in the linguistic community considered as a collective body ; but that collective body divides the “labor” of knowing and employing these various parts of the “meaning” of “gold”. (Putnam 1975b: 228)

    Since the members of the linguistic community, considered as a collective body, do not possess the language separately, they are compelled to cooperate. Later on this thought has been reformulated by Putnam clearly and explicitly:

    There is a division of linguistic labor. Language is a form of cooperative activity, not an essentially individualistic activity. Part of what is wrong with the Aristotelian picture is that it suggests that everything that is necessary for the use of language is stored in each individual mind; but no actual language works that way. (Putnam 2001: 25)

    Putnam’s formulations can be generalized thus:

    (T1) division of linguistic labor prevails in every linguistic community and there are terms the application rules of which are known only by few experts, and thus these terms can only be used by others due to the cooperation with these experts.

    The proposition states that the social aspect is not just necessary or derivative but the essential feature of language. Language can only be possessed collectively by agents engaged in collective work with shared tasks, tools and specialized knowledge." (pp.36-38)

    "It is easy to see that Lukács expounded the same theory concerning the social character of language. I believe that Lukács would have accepted Putnam’s famous externality thesis too, according to which “meanings are not in the head.” Th is is but a the stronger way of stating that meanings are not identical with the individuals’ ideas about things, and that the utterer’s psychological condition does not defi ne what she “means.” [...]

    Putnam suggests that relying on the concept of division of linguistic labor marks the division between the traditional philosophies of language and the more appropriate conceptions recognizing that language is predetermined by world and society.

    Ignoring the division of linguistic labor is ignoring the social dimenson of cognition; ignoring what we have called the indexicality of most words is ignoring the contribution of environment. Traditional philosophy of language, like much traditional philosophy, leaves out other people and the world ; a better philosophy and a better science of language must encompass both. (Putnam 1975b: 274)

    Putnam thus calls for such a materialist philosophy that recognizes the social dimension of language and its ontological dependence on the world. It should be noted, however, that from a Lukácsian and Marxist point of view his conception has a serious defect, because it does not take into account the problem of production and the distinction between technical and social division of labor. Th erefore, proposition (T1) must be transformed and completed in the following way:

    (T1’) Technical division of labor is the feature of every single linguistic community, for the linguistic agents’ knowledge of producing and using the linguistic tools (terms) are possessed only by few agents. Other members of the community acquire this knowledge only in cooperation with such agents.

    This amendment integrates the notion of “production” into (T1), and shows that Putnam applies exclusively one kind of division of labor (though historically a universal kind) to language.

    It was Rossi-Landi who, going beyond this, created a semiotic theory relying upon the principles specifi ed in (T1’). To this can be added the following theses:

    (T2) Technical division of labor, which is the feature of every linguistic community, usually has the form of social division of labor. This is to say that speakers’ (the linguistic agents’) place in the division of (linguistic) labor is determined by the structure of class stratification of the society.

    (T3) Due to the social division of labor prevalent in numerous linguistic communities, only few speakers can define, monopolize and control the knowledge necessary for the production and application of linguistic tools (terms).

    (T1’), (T2) and (T3) suffi  ciently describe Rossi-Landi’s linguistic theory only if we postulate the homology of material and linguistic production too. Without further analysis I just want to note that the three theorems presuppose the homology of linguistic and material division of labor. Without accepting that linguistic agency is articulated by material production, the discourse about linguistic labor and division of linguistic labor will be purely metaphorical.

    The significance of taking into account the social aspect of the division of linguistic labor besides the technical aspects is that it highlights the core concept of Rossi-Landi’s philosophy of language—the foundations of the critic of linguistic alienation and exploitation." (pp.38-40)

    "This critic can be considered as a continuation of the Marxian–Lukácsian analyses of the eff ects of reifi cation upon language, the theoretical and practical importance of which has not faded to this very day. Debunking linguistic alienation and exploitation, that is critic of language, has at the same time always been the critique of society and ideology, or expression of critical thinking, at least. Now would be time to revive this tradition. According to Rossi-Landi’s theory it is easy to see that information society entails not only the promise of more democracy but also the threat of linguistic alienation. The threat of division of linguistic labor turning into social division of labor, and the danger that exclusive groups appropriate the control over the tools and content of communication, or the right of defi ning linguistic meanings, subsist as before.

    Returning to the division of labor, or—in more general terms—to the phenomenon of interrelated teleological acts, it must be remarked that the ultimate and global objective of all collective activity can be attained only through the conscious or unconscious interaction of the individuals. That is precisely what is caught in another defi nition-like statement of Lukács :

    Originally language is a social means to cause certain teleological settings (“teleologische Setzungen”) whose aim is to induce other people to execute certain teleological settings.

    Recall that it does not follow from Lukács’s thesis that teleology becomes absolute, or its signifi cance is exaggerated in an idealist manner. For his statements do not include the claim that language as the product of the teleology of labor and as the means of the execution of the teleology of labor is in any sense a result of conscious creation and a prior setting of objectives. As was shown above, the whole of Lukács’s explanation of language is footed on different grounds. Th e most important of its moral is the necessity to understand language as a category of being before any interpretation of it as a category of social and individual consciousness. Even if Lukács’s analyses do not offer concrete means to describe the formal characteristics of language and even if some of the details of his theory may well be criticized in the light of anthropology and formal theories of language, the above statement can be overlooked by none who intend to fi nd a place for the issue of language among the problems which can be seen as important parts of the legacy of Marxism." (pp.40-41)
    -János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács, Palgrave Macmillan, 2014, 144 pages.


    _________________
    « La question n’est pas de constater que les gens vivent plus ou moins pauvrement, mais toujours d’une manière qui leur échappe. » -Guy Debord, Critique de la séparation (1961).

    « Rien de grand ne s’est jamais accompli dans le monde sans passion. » -Hegel, La Raison dans l'Histoire.

    « Mais parfois le plus clair regard aime aussi l’ombre. » -Friedrich Hölderlin, "Pain et Vin".

    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Johnathan R. Razorback
    Admin


    Messages : 20946
    Date d'inscription : 12/08/2013
    Localisation : France

    János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács Empty Re: János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács

    Message par Johnathan R. Razorback Dim 29 Déc - 20:03

    [Chapitre 3 - Lukács’s Conception of Science]

    "A perusal of Lukács’s various essays in the volume is enough to reveal that he touches upon almost all the central problems of philosophy of science, problems that were rooted in the social and intellectual context of the day and that still occupy a prominent place aft er the “Kuhnian turn” in that branch of philosophy. Seen from the angle of the history of science, that period was characterized by a revolt against positivism, as today’s post-Kuhnian tendencies are strongly anti-positivistic. History and Class Consciousness was also a product of that revolt against positivist philosophy of science, among other things. Th is is testifi ed to by the fact that Lukács, like many of his contemporaries, held the positivist ideal of science to be identical with the idea of science. His criticism of positivism is thus signifi cantly framed as the criticism of science. On the other hand, he also identifies the positivist ideal of science with bourgeois rationality. Consequently, his criticism of science and of positivism is transposed into the criticism of bourgeois reason. Again, this is well demonstrated by his reliance on the tradition of the Geisteswissenschaft en and contemporary anti-positivist authors (most visibly on Max Weber) in criticizing bourgeois rationality and science.

    The variety of themes related to philosophy of science in History and Class Consciousness is indeed remarkable : methodology of social science; the epistemological and methodological dualism of natural and social sciences ; the problem of scientific facts ; the relationship between science and society (the internal link between the structure of scientific knowledge and the fundamental traits of capitalism) ; the nature of historical knowledge, the relation of philosophy to the special social sciences ; the nature of scientific laws ; the relationship between empirical data and theory; and so on. To this list, far from being complete, one could add the problem of scientific rationality as well as the question whether the terms and concepts employed in the scientific description of facts ought to fall in with the subjective representations of those facts, that is, with the terms in which the producers of the facts interpret their situation, and within it, themselves. Th e metaphysical and historical philosophical thesis that historical knowledge is self-knowledge and that knowledge formed of an object changes the object itself can also be viewed as pertaining to the philosophy of science.

    The logical domain of the answers to these questions is defi ned along the dimensions of appearance and reality, externality and internality, part and whole. To these can be added the dichotomy of statics and dynamics (factual and processual character). The answers Lukács gives along the different dimensions are consistent and, as a whole, form a coherent theory of science. In the first analysis, this theory simply appears to be anti-positivistic, for a number of Lukács’s assertions (in proper logical reconstruction) are also found in the core of other anti-positivist philosophies of science, both traditional and modern. The kind of dualism that he embraces in firmly contrasting natural with social science is no less part of a more general anti-positivism than his negation of the isolated or theory-independent nature of facts. (Lukács’s position concerning the relationship between empirical data and theory can be translated into the language of today’s philosophy of science as denying the existence of an empirical basis independent of theory as well as the possibility of a neutral language of observation, and asserting the “theory-ladenness” of the empirical terms, etc.)

    Apart from the commitment to revolutionary practice, the philosophy of science discernible in History and Class Consciousness is theoretically distinguished from other brands of anti-positivism by the use of the categories of reification, the identity of subject and object, and totality on the one hand, and on the other, especially by the way in which Lukács relates science to the structure of a given society and to a socially and historically distinguished point of view." (pp.46-47)

    "Lukács asserts more than the mere autonomy of social scientific knowledge. He explicitly claims the autonomy of social science with regard to the model of natural science to be characteristic of proletarian science, ignoring thus the fact that he himself adopted the idea from bourgeois thinkers seeking independent grounds for social science. His stance is based on the assumption that natural science is intrinsically related to capitalism. From this, it immediately follows for him that it is a typically bourgeois attempt to extend the ideal of natural scientific knowledge to the study of society [...] Thus, the emancipation of proletarian class consciousness presupposes the independence of societal knowledge from natural science.

    It emerges by now that, as has been mentioned, Lukács necessarily regards positivism as the typical philosophy of capitalism. But what should the affinity between natural science and capitalism mean ? For Lukács, it basically means that capitalism produces phenomena in reality in the same way as natural science produces its “pure” facts in the cognitive sphere. Both spheres resort to the method of isolating abstraction “when a phenomenon of the real world is placed (in thought or in reality) into an environment where its laws can be inspected without outside interference.” Both areas are also characterized by “reducing the phenomena to their purely quantitative essence”

    Lukács’s analysis seems to be correct; it essentially carries the insight that natural science represents a type of rationality that is the historical product of the capitalist organization of society. There remain, nevertheless, certain questions open in respect of the affi  nity between natural science and capitalism and the relationship between natural and social science.

    Such questions are whether natural science depends on capitalism only for its origin or also as a precondition of its possibility. Therefore, if the facts of natural science are analogous to the facts of the social world of reifi cation, does then the abolishment of reification not remove the grounds of the natural scientific attitude ? Can natural scientific knowledge be adequate at all if it is itself the product of a particular, socially determined perspective ? Or is it the case that the bourgeoisie is incapable only of comprehending its own social relationship while its particular class position and point of view enable it to develop adequate natural scientific methods ?

    Lukács does not raise such questions explicitly, but he seems to recognize the validity of natural science and uncritically endorses the generally accepted conception of its development. He writes,

    The methodology of the natural sciences which forms the methodological ideal of every fetishistic science and every kind of revisionism rejects the idea of contradiction and antagonism in its subject matter. If, despite this, contradictions spring up between particular theories, this only proves that our knowledge is as yet imperfect. Contradictions between theories show that these theories have reached their natural limits; they must therefore be transformed and subsumed under even wider theories in which the contradictions finally disappear.

    All this corresponds well to the traditional positivist conception, surviving almost up to our day, that the progress of science is a cumulative development that leads to more and more general theories, while earlier theories are incorporated as parts in the later ones. Lukács’s strategy does not differ in this respect from that of such thinkers, active at the turn of the century as Rickert, Dilthey or Weber, who called for the independent grounding of the social, cultural or historical science without challenging the accepted views on natural scientific knowledge. However, contrary to the neo-Kantian and geisteswissenschaft liche approaches, Lukács seeks the specific difference of social scientific knowledge from natural science not in “individuating concept formation” or in understanding as opposed to explanation but in the fact that “in the case of social reality these contradictions are not a sign of the imperfect understanding of society: on the contrary, they belong to the nature of reality itself and to the nature of capitalism”." (pp.48-49)

    "He holds that natural science, in spite of its fundamental affi  nity to capitalism, is a source of adequate knowledge. On the other hand, social science can have no claim to validity unless it transcends capitalism. To achieve this, it must part with the ideal of natural scientific knowledge, which is based on the structures of reifi cation and which essentially cannot accommodate contradiction. Th e proper knowledge of  the structure of society presupposes the unveiling of reifi cation on which natural science is based and demands the acceptance of contradictions as real contradictions.

    The way Lukács opposes natural to social science explains the fact that the real target of his radical criticism is social science conceived as dominated by the methodology of the natural sciences. We can only remark here that, according to his critique of science, the social precondition to statistical or other sorts of exactitude is “the fact that capitalist society is predisposed to harmonize with scientifi c method” [...] The striving for exactitude causes “science” to be ahistorical and, on the other hand, runs the risk that “it thereby takes its stand simply and dogmatically on the basis of capitalist society” [...] To make matters worse, science remains a captive of appearance, of “the form in which the phenomena are immediately given” [...] It is easily recognized that, from the epistemological point of view, the real target of this critique of science is fi rst and foremost empiricism and that the conception Lukács sets at vaiance to bourgeois science  is deeply anti-empiricistic. His critique fi nds its continuation in the anti-empiricism of later radical critics of scientifi c methodology. What Lukács did not realize was that a criticism of empiricism cannot be partial and restricted only to the social sciences. It is no accident that today’s radical philosophies of science attack empiricism in its safest stronghold, natural science.

    Here we should note, however, that the critique of science given in History and Class Consciousness is extraordinarily close to that appearing in another great work of the interwar period, namely The Crisis of European Science and Transcendental Phenomenology [...] Some—Mihály Vajda, for instance—have even stated that “the critiques of science in the two works are identical” (Vajda 1983: 109). Indeed, it is easy to draw parallels between many aspects of the analyses made by Lukács and Husserl. As Vajda shows, both Husserl and Lukács are of the view that “science is unable to assume the standpoint of the totality” (Vajda 1983: 109). Further, both philosophers vehemently criticize quantifi cation methods and the associated mentality. In their view, the sciences have been taken over by a false rationalism. It is a one-sided, formal, objectivistic and naturalistic rationalism, the corollary of which is necessarily irrationalism: the irrationality of the whole.

    The critique of science of both phenomenology and Lukácsian Marxism reveals this kind of scientistic worldview to be “false consciousness,” which must be contrasted, in their view, with the positions of holism and totality as well as the denial of the dichotomous separation of science and philosophy." (pp.49-50)

    "As regards the claim of social science to autonomy, it does not imply that the extension of natural science as such to the societal sphere is responsible for the distortion of social scientifi c knowledge. In other words, the fact that an ideal of science stems from natural science does not guarantee the applicability of that ideal even to natural science itself. A scientific ideal as a framework of general epistemological presuppositions is liable to criticism independently of its application in either the natural or the social sciences. If, for example, the ideal proves to thwart social science, this helps to identify it as untenable in general. In this respect, among others we may refer to Collingwood. He was right in maintaining that it is an epistemological model incompatible with the mere existence of history that places in the starting point of every cognitive situation the simultaneous presence of the subject and the object of cognition, observational descriptions and actual sense-data. Th at model taken from natural science indeed misrepresents natural science itself (see Collingwood 1946).

    At any rate, Lukács’s critique of science turns out to be justifi ed in several respects. Th e 20th-century development of science has shown a tendency toward a greater and greater degree for research to be partitioned into isolated areas that can rarely, or oft en not at all, be seen to be interdependent. The drawbacks, such as the futility of segments deprived of their contexts, need not be detailed here. Th ey are no less characteristic of natural science than of social science.

    However, the conception of science traceable to History and Class Consciousness has also initiated a rather problematic tradition to Marxism.

    The dualistic philosophy of science analyzed above greatly contributed to establishing the view that the social sciences are of a merely ideological and class character while the natural sciences are free from any social or ideological determinants. (Th is kind of scientism became an element of Stalinism even though various branches of natural science were also labeled “bourgeois pseudo-science” in the Stalinist era.)" (pp.51-52)

    "Within that work, the category of totality appears to have special functions. It serves as a basis of the theory of potential consciousness and of the thesis that the adequate knowledge of society is at the same time the self-knowledge of the proletariat. (On a more general level, this thesis entails that adequate knowledge is only possible as adequate self-knowledge: “For every piece of historical knowledge is an act of self-knowledge” [...] Only the proletariat is capable of this.) It is widely known that within these interrelations the category of totality is the main analytic tool applied to proletarian consciousness, this function of it having been studied by many, from Lucien Goldmann to István Hermann. But the function it plays in the fi eld of philosophy of science in the more specific sense has received less attention.

    Speaking in terms of philosophy of science, we may say that the point of view of totality is first of all an expression of Lukács’s anti-empiricism. The main function of that category in this area is to serve as the foundation of Lukács’s idea of science. More precisely, he intends to infer from it the possibility of a social science that applies the methodology of natural science and thus is trapped within the limitations of mere facticity and reifi ed appearance.

    As latter-day methodological debates (like the so-called Positivismusstreit) indicate, many authors doubt if the category of totality can be invested with some non-mystical, scientific sense. I myself would not go as far as that. Nowadays, when the hermeneutic approach is making its comeback, it is easier to argue that any empirical investigation can only take on significance within a wider context of sense. Conceiving any results of observation, measurement or experiments as data requires interpretation that is only possible through that wide context of sense. It remains a problem that it is very difficult to specify the conditions under which “totality” or the “wide context of sense” can become operational, that is, translated into practical procedures. History and Class Consciousness off ers few guidelines in this direction. One rather fi nds in it problematic claims that, for the most part, were not confirmed by subsequent scientific developments." (pp.52-53)
    -János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács, Palgrave Macmillan, 2014, 144 pages.


    _________________
    « La question n’est pas de constater que les gens vivent plus ou moins pauvrement, mais toujours d’une manière qui leur échappe. » -Guy Debord, Critique de la séparation (1961).

    « Rien de grand ne s’est jamais accompli dans le monde sans passion. » -Hegel, La Raison dans l'Histoire.

    « Mais parfois le plus clair regard aime aussi l’ombre. » -Friedrich Hölderlin, "Pain et Vin".


    Contenu sponsorisé


    János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács Empty Re: János Kelemen, The Rationalism of Georg Lukács

    Message par Contenu sponsorisé


      La date/heure actuelle est Jeu 16 Jan - 1:17